We can't exactly draw a line of length square root of 2 but can be constructed using Pythagoras theorem in an...












-1












$begingroup$


We can't exactly draw a line of length square root of 2 but in an isosceles right angle triangle of sides 1 unit each, the length of hypotenuse will be the square root of 2. Now does it mean we can get the line of exact such length?



How is it possible? How can we get a line of exact length square root of 2 which we can't construct exactly due to its infinite decimal expansion? So does Pythagoras theorem mislead us or create a paradox?










share|cite|improve this question









$endgroup$








  • 2




    $begingroup$
    The decimal expansion of a number has nothing to do with drawing a line segment between two points. By the way, we are talking about ideal lines and points here. The lines and points that you make with a pencil and a ruler are not really lines and points. A real line has no thickness. A real point has no width or height.
    $endgroup$
    – steven gregory
    Dec 16 '18 at 2:32






  • 1




    $begingroup$
    "We can't exactly draw a line of length square root of $2$"? Who said so? What reason did they give? What is the relevance of the "infinite decimal expansion"? (Note, the number $frac13$ also has an "infinite decimal expansion"!) Please edit the question to make it clear what you mean.
    $endgroup$
    – David K
    Dec 16 '18 at 3:15


















-1












$begingroup$


We can't exactly draw a line of length square root of 2 but in an isosceles right angle triangle of sides 1 unit each, the length of hypotenuse will be the square root of 2. Now does it mean we can get the line of exact such length?



How is it possible? How can we get a line of exact length square root of 2 which we can't construct exactly due to its infinite decimal expansion? So does Pythagoras theorem mislead us or create a paradox?










share|cite|improve this question









$endgroup$








  • 2




    $begingroup$
    The decimal expansion of a number has nothing to do with drawing a line segment between two points. By the way, we are talking about ideal lines and points here. The lines and points that you make with a pencil and a ruler are not really lines and points. A real line has no thickness. A real point has no width or height.
    $endgroup$
    – steven gregory
    Dec 16 '18 at 2:32






  • 1




    $begingroup$
    "We can't exactly draw a line of length square root of $2$"? Who said so? What reason did they give? What is the relevance of the "infinite decimal expansion"? (Note, the number $frac13$ also has an "infinite decimal expansion"!) Please edit the question to make it clear what you mean.
    $endgroup$
    – David K
    Dec 16 '18 at 3:15
















-1












-1








-1





$begingroup$


We can't exactly draw a line of length square root of 2 but in an isosceles right angle triangle of sides 1 unit each, the length of hypotenuse will be the square root of 2. Now does it mean we can get the line of exact such length?



How is it possible? How can we get a line of exact length square root of 2 which we can't construct exactly due to its infinite decimal expansion? So does Pythagoras theorem mislead us or create a paradox?










share|cite|improve this question









$endgroup$




We can't exactly draw a line of length square root of 2 but in an isosceles right angle triangle of sides 1 unit each, the length of hypotenuse will be the square root of 2. Now does it mean we can get the line of exact such length?



How is it possible? How can we get a line of exact length square root of 2 which we can't construct exactly due to its infinite decimal expansion? So does Pythagoras theorem mislead us or create a paradox?







geometry irrational-numbers pythagorean-triples






share|cite|improve this question













share|cite|improve this question











share|cite|improve this question




share|cite|improve this question










asked Dec 16 '18 at 1:52









IdddfbefIdddfbef

32




32








  • 2




    $begingroup$
    The decimal expansion of a number has nothing to do with drawing a line segment between two points. By the way, we are talking about ideal lines and points here. The lines and points that you make with a pencil and a ruler are not really lines and points. A real line has no thickness. A real point has no width or height.
    $endgroup$
    – steven gregory
    Dec 16 '18 at 2:32






  • 1




    $begingroup$
    "We can't exactly draw a line of length square root of $2$"? Who said so? What reason did they give? What is the relevance of the "infinite decimal expansion"? (Note, the number $frac13$ also has an "infinite decimal expansion"!) Please edit the question to make it clear what you mean.
    $endgroup$
    – David K
    Dec 16 '18 at 3:15
















  • 2




    $begingroup$
    The decimal expansion of a number has nothing to do with drawing a line segment between two points. By the way, we are talking about ideal lines and points here. The lines and points that you make with a pencil and a ruler are not really lines and points. A real line has no thickness. A real point has no width or height.
    $endgroup$
    – steven gregory
    Dec 16 '18 at 2:32






  • 1




    $begingroup$
    "We can't exactly draw a line of length square root of $2$"? Who said so? What reason did they give? What is the relevance of the "infinite decimal expansion"? (Note, the number $frac13$ also has an "infinite decimal expansion"!) Please edit the question to make it clear what you mean.
    $endgroup$
    – David K
    Dec 16 '18 at 3:15










2




2




$begingroup$
The decimal expansion of a number has nothing to do with drawing a line segment between two points. By the way, we are talking about ideal lines and points here. The lines and points that you make with a pencil and a ruler are not really lines and points. A real line has no thickness. A real point has no width or height.
$endgroup$
– steven gregory
Dec 16 '18 at 2:32




$begingroup$
The decimal expansion of a number has nothing to do with drawing a line segment between two points. By the way, we are talking about ideal lines and points here. The lines and points that you make with a pencil and a ruler are not really lines and points. A real line has no thickness. A real point has no width or height.
$endgroup$
– steven gregory
Dec 16 '18 at 2:32




1




1




$begingroup$
"We can't exactly draw a line of length square root of $2$"? Who said so? What reason did they give? What is the relevance of the "infinite decimal expansion"? (Note, the number $frac13$ also has an "infinite decimal expansion"!) Please edit the question to make it clear what you mean.
$endgroup$
– David K
Dec 16 '18 at 3:15






$begingroup$
"We can't exactly draw a line of length square root of $2$"? Who said so? What reason did they give? What is the relevance of the "infinite decimal expansion"? (Note, the number $frac13$ also has an "infinite decimal expansion"!) Please edit the question to make it clear what you mean.
$endgroup$
– David K
Dec 16 '18 at 3:15












2 Answers
2






active

oldest

votes


















2












$begingroup$

The apparent paradox results from the difference between the ideal triangle you can construct in your mind, with a hypotenuse of $sqrt{2}$, and an actual figure that you can draw, where making a two legs of exactly unit length, meeting at a perfectly right angle, can be approximated, but not actually accomplished. Thus any figure you draw will not feature a line of length exactly $sqrt{2}$, even though the perfect triangle you can conceive of will.






share|cite|improve this answer









$endgroup$





















    2












    $begingroup$

    A lot of numbers are called "constructible", in that, if $n$ is constructible, then we can find a construction in which a line of $n$ units can be made. Granted, this is not a trivial task depending on the construction and number involved.



    In the sense of construction and only drawing a line, then the only thing we can draw "exactly" is a line segment which we would denote as our unit, essentially $1$. Everything else requires some method of construction. We can make $2$ by appending two unit lengths; we can make $1/2$ by bisecting a unit length.



    The only things we're given is a unit length, our straightedge, and a compass. Nothing else; take out the construction and we only have a unit. (And you could even argue drawing the line itself is a unit.) From there, we can find constructible numbers $n$, which are $n$ unit lengths long.



    It will also be helpful to note that we cannot use rulers. I mean, they can be used, insofar as being a straightedge, but we're not allowed to use them to measure out, say, $2$ inches or whatever. This is because the ruler might be flawed, your line might be flawed - it could be too long by ever-so-many atom-widths if you want to be pedantic; what temperature it is could affect the scaling even if only minutely; blah blah blah. In constructions, we effectively view the tools and our execution of the construction as "perfect", free of human errors like these, if just in the theoretical sense.



    Why am I rambling on about constructions?



    Because that is at the core of why you might say you cannot draw a line of length $sqrt2$ units - because I think you're looking at the ruler. You look at it and go "I can't get to it because it's irrational. I can only guessimate in halves or quarters or whatever's on my ruler, I can only make rational estimations. I cannot find square root of $2$ just by drawing a line."



    And you're right - you can't make $sqrt2$ just by drawing a line. You can't make anything by drawing a line, except your unit, assuming - again - the inherent perfectness of construction and technique and not knowing exact lengths a priori.



    The only length you can draw, without other aides, is a line $1$ unit long.



    Seems weird when you say it but that's what it comes down to.



    So how do we draw others? We use constructions. We make use of geometric principles to demonstrate other numbers are "constructible." These numbers can be constructed, made. Given a unit, straightedge, and compass, we can make a line $n$ units long, where $n$ is constructible.



    This gives rise to the constructible numbers. Like the real numbers, they form a field: you can multiply and add any two constructible numbers to get another one. You can also divide and subtract them.



    What are some examples of constructible numbers? Well...




    • All of the natural numbers (just keep appending lines of length $1$ to each)

    • All of the rational numbers (bisections and appending of various lengths)

    • Square roots of rational numbers (the isosceles right triangle of side length $a$ suffices to give a hypotenuse of length $sqrt a$)


    These are not the only examples; the article I linked discusses them at further length. There are some numbers known to not be constructible:




    • $sqrt[3]2$

    • $sqrt pi$


    • $cos left( arccos(x)/3 right)$ for constructible $x$ (related to how angles generally cannot be trisected)


    I think that's enough rambling. In short:




    • In reality, with only a straightedge, you are given a unit length, representative of $1$

    • With compass and straightedge, you can make the constructible numbers (again, see https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Constructible_number for more info)

    • Constructions cannot use rulers to measure out lengths: we can only have a straightedge and compass, and the former allows us a starting, unit length.

    • In constructions, at least analyzing them in theoretical realm (rather than making practical use of them), we look at them in the sense of being "perfect" and absent of human errors. There are definitely rational approximations for $pi$ or $sqrt 2$ that are really, REALLY good (look into continued fractions if you're curious), and it shouldn't be hard to convince yourself of our ability to draw those. But constructions - if perfect, if idealized, if absent of error - also allows us to represent irrational numbers.

    • We can draw right triangles via a construction and isosceles right triangles in particular - this isn't at all difficult - so we can draw lines of $sqrt q$ for any rational $q$ units. This includes $q=2$. Of course, if you do it in real life, then it's not going to be exactly right, no measurement is. But in looking at constructions and constructible numbers, we ignore that and look at a theoretical, perfect, idealized case where these human errors aren't present. In that sense, $sqrt 2$ is absolutely drawable (when you use a construction to get a right triangle). Of course in real life imperfections arise everywhere - but mathematics is kinda beautiful in that sense, it allows us to consider the idealized situation too, as well as make it practical, give us "close enough" solutions to real life.






    share|cite|improve this answer









    $endgroup$













      Your Answer





      StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function () {
      return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function () {
      StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix) {
      StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
      });
      });
      }, "mathjax-editing");

      StackExchange.ready(function() {
      var channelOptions = {
      tags: "".split(" "),
      id: "69"
      };
      initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

      StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function() {
      // Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
      if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled) {
      StackExchange.using("snippets", function() {
      createEditor();
      });
      }
      else {
      createEditor();
      }
      });

      function createEditor() {
      StackExchange.prepareEditor({
      heartbeatType: 'answer',
      autoActivateHeartbeat: false,
      convertImagesToLinks: true,
      noModals: true,
      showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
      reputationToPostImages: 10,
      bindNavPrevention: true,
      postfix: "",
      imageUploader: {
      brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
      contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
      allowUrls: true
      },
      noCode: true, onDemand: true,
      discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
      ,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
      });


      }
      });














      draft saved

      draft discarded


















      StackExchange.ready(
      function () {
      StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3042149%2fwe-cant-exactly-draw-a-line-of-length-square-root-of-2-but-can-be-constructed-u%23new-answer', 'question_page');
      }
      );

      Post as a guest















      Required, but never shown

























      2 Answers
      2






      active

      oldest

      votes








      2 Answers
      2






      active

      oldest

      votes









      active

      oldest

      votes






      active

      oldest

      votes









      2












      $begingroup$

      The apparent paradox results from the difference between the ideal triangle you can construct in your mind, with a hypotenuse of $sqrt{2}$, and an actual figure that you can draw, where making a two legs of exactly unit length, meeting at a perfectly right angle, can be approximated, but not actually accomplished. Thus any figure you draw will not feature a line of length exactly $sqrt{2}$, even though the perfect triangle you can conceive of will.






      share|cite|improve this answer









      $endgroup$


















        2












        $begingroup$

        The apparent paradox results from the difference between the ideal triangle you can construct in your mind, with a hypotenuse of $sqrt{2}$, and an actual figure that you can draw, where making a two legs of exactly unit length, meeting at a perfectly right angle, can be approximated, but not actually accomplished. Thus any figure you draw will not feature a line of length exactly $sqrt{2}$, even though the perfect triangle you can conceive of will.






        share|cite|improve this answer









        $endgroup$
















          2












          2








          2





          $begingroup$

          The apparent paradox results from the difference between the ideal triangle you can construct in your mind, with a hypotenuse of $sqrt{2}$, and an actual figure that you can draw, where making a two legs of exactly unit length, meeting at a perfectly right angle, can be approximated, but not actually accomplished. Thus any figure you draw will not feature a line of length exactly $sqrt{2}$, even though the perfect triangle you can conceive of will.






          share|cite|improve this answer









          $endgroup$



          The apparent paradox results from the difference between the ideal triangle you can construct in your mind, with a hypotenuse of $sqrt{2}$, and an actual figure that you can draw, where making a two legs of exactly unit length, meeting at a perfectly right angle, can be approximated, but not actually accomplished. Thus any figure you draw will not feature a line of length exactly $sqrt{2}$, even though the perfect triangle you can conceive of will.







          share|cite|improve this answer












          share|cite|improve this answer



          share|cite|improve this answer










          answered Dec 16 '18 at 2:08









          Keith BackmanKeith Backman

          1,1371712




          1,1371712























              2












              $begingroup$

              A lot of numbers are called "constructible", in that, if $n$ is constructible, then we can find a construction in which a line of $n$ units can be made. Granted, this is not a trivial task depending on the construction and number involved.



              In the sense of construction and only drawing a line, then the only thing we can draw "exactly" is a line segment which we would denote as our unit, essentially $1$. Everything else requires some method of construction. We can make $2$ by appending two unit lengths; we can make $1/2$ by bisecting a unit length.



              The only things we're given is a unit length, our straightedge, and a compass. Nothing else; take out the construction and we only have a unit. (And you could even argue drawing the line itself is a unit.) From there, we can find constructible numbers $n$, which are $n$ unit lengths long.



              It will also be helpful to note that we cannot use rulers. I mean, they can be used, insofar as being a straightedge, but we're not allowed to use them to measure out, say, $2$ inches or whatever. This is because the ruler might be flawed, your line might be flawed - it could be too long by ever-so-many atom-widths if you want to be pedantic; what temperature it is could affect the scaling even if only minutely; blah blah blah. In constructions, we effectively view the tools and our execution of the construction as "perfect", free of human errors like these, if just in the theoretical sense.



              Why am I rambling on about constructions?



              Because that is at the core of why you might say you cannot draw a line of length $sqrt2$ units - because I think you're looking at the ruler. You look at it and go "I can't get to it because it's irrational. I can only guessimate in halves or quarters or whatever's on my ruler, I can only make rational estimations. I cannot find square root of $2$ just by drawing a line."



              And you're right - you can't make $sqrt2$ just by drawing a line. You can't make anything by drawing a line, except your unit, assuming - again - the inherent perfectness of construction and technique and not knowing exact lengths a priori.



              The only length you can draw, without other aides, is a line $1$ unit long.



              Seems weird when you say it but that's what it comes down to.



              So how do we draw others? We use constructions. We make use of geometric principles to demonstrate other numbers are "constructible." These numbers can be constructed, made. Given a unit, straightedge, and compass, we can make a line $n$ units long, where $n$ is constructible.



              This gives rise to the constructible numbers. Like the real numbers, they form a field: you can multiply and add any two constructible numbers to get another one. You can also divide and subtract them.



              What are some examples of constructible numbers? Well...




              • All of the natural numbers (just keep appending lines of length $1$ to each)

              • All of the rational numbers (bisections and appending of various lengths)

              • Square roots of rational numbers (the isosceles right triangle of side length $a$ suffices to give a hypotenuse of length $sqrt a$)


              These are not the only examples; the article I linked discusses them at further length. There are some numbers known to not be constructible:




              • $sqrt[3]2$

              • $sqrt pi$


              • $cos left( arccos(x)/3 right)$ for constructible $x$ (related to how angles generally cannot be trisected)


              I think that's enough rambling. In short:




              • In reality, with only a straightedge, you are given a unit length, representative of $1$

              • With compass and straightedge, you can make the constructible numbers (again, see https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Constructible_number for more info)

              • Constructions cannot use rulers to measure out lengths: we can only have a straightedge and compass, and the former allows us a starting, unit length.

              • In constructions, at least analyzing them in theoretical realm (rather than making practical use of them), we look at them in the sense of being "perfect" and absent of human errors. There are definitely rational approximations for $pi$ or $sqrt 2$ that are really, REALLY good (look into continued fractions if you're curious), and it shouldn't be hard to convince yourself of our ability to draw those. But constructions - if perfect, if idealized, if absent of error - also allows us to represent irrational numbers.

              • We can draw right triangles via a construction and isosceles right triangles in particular - this isn't at all difficult - so we can draw lines of $sqrt q$ for any rational $q$ units. This includes $q=2$. Of course, if you do it in real life, then it's not going to be exactly right, no measurement is. But in looking at constructions and constructible numbers, we ignore that and look at a theoretical, perfect, idealized case where these human errors aren't present. In that sense, $sqrt 2$ is absolutely drawable (when you use a construction to get a right triangle). Of course in real life imperfections arise everywhere - but mathematics is kinda beautiful in that sense, it allows us to consider the idealized situation too, as well as make it practical, give us "close enough" solutions to real life.






              share|cite|improve this answer









              $endgroup$


















                2












                $begingroup$

                A lot of numbers are called "constructible", in that, if $n$ is constructible, then we can find a construction in which a line of $n$ units can be made. Granted, this is not a trivial task depending on the construction and number involved.



                In the sense of construction and only drawing a line, then the only thing we can draw "exactly" is a line segment which we would denote as our unit, essentially $1$. Everything else requires some method of construction. We can make $2$ by appending two unit lengths; we can make $1/2$ by bisecting a unit length.



                The only things we're given is a unit length, our straightedge, and a compass. Nothing else; take out the construction and we only have a unit. (And you could even argue drawing the line itself is a unit.) From there, we can find constructible numbers $n$, which are $n$ unit lengths long.



                It will also be helpful to note that we cannot use rulers. I mean, they can be used, insofar as being a straightedge, but we're not allowed to use them to measure out, say, $2$ inches or whatever. This is because the ruler might be flawed, your line might be flawed - it could be too long by ever-so-many atom-widths if you want to be pedantic; what temperature it is could affect the scaling even if only minutely; blah blah blah. In constructions, we effectively view the tools and our execution of the construction as "perfect", free of human errors like these, if just in the theoretical sense.



                Why am I rambling on about constructions?



                Because that is at the core of why you might say you cannot draw a line of length $sqrt2$ units - because I think you're looking at the ruler. You look at it and go "I can't get to it because it's irrational. I can only guessimate in halves or quarters or whatever's on my ruler, I can only make rational estimations. I cannot find square root of $2$ just by drawing a line."



                And you're right - you can't make $sqrt2$ just by drawing a line. You can't make anything by drawing a line, except your unit, assuming - again - the inherent perfectness of construction and technique and not knowing exact lengths a priori.



                The only length you can draw, without other aides, is a line $1$ unit long.



                Seems weird when you say it but that's what it comes down to.



                So how do we draw others? We use constructions. We make use of geometric principles to demonstrate other numbers are "constructible." These numbers can be constructed, made. Given a unit, straightedge, and compass, we can make a line $n$ units long, where $n$ is constructible.



                This gives rise to the constructible numbers. Like the real numbers, they form a field: you can multiply and add any two constructible numbers to get another one. You can also divide and subtract them.



                What are some examples of constructible numbers? Well...




                • All of the natural numbers (just keep appending lines of length $1$ to each)

                • All of the rational numbers (bisections and appending of various lengths)

                • Square roots of rational numbers (the isosceles right triangle of side length $a$ suffices to give a hypotenuse of length $sqrt a$)


                These are not the only examples; the article I linked discusses them at further length. There are some numbers known to not be constructible:




                • $sqrt[3]2$

                • $sqrt pi$


                • $cos left( arccos(x)/3 right)$ for constructible $x$ (related to how angles generally cannot be trisected)


                I think that's enough rambling. In short:




                • In reality, with only a straightedge, you are given a unit length, representative of $1$

                • With compass and straightedge, you can make the constructible numbers (again, see https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Constructible_number for more info)

                • Constructions cannot use rulers to measure out lengths: we can only have a straightedge and compass, and the former allows us a starting, unit length.

                • In constructions, at least analyzing them in theoretical realm (rather than making practical use of them), we look at them in the sense of being "perfect" and absent of human errors. There are definitely rational approximations for $pi$ or $sqrt 2$ that are really, REALLY good (look into continued fractions if you're curious), and it shouldn't be hard to convince yourself of our ability to draw those. But constructions - if perfect, if idealized, if absent of error - also allows us to represent irrational numbers.

                • We can draw right triangles via a construction and isosceles right triangles in particular - this isn't at all difficult - so we can draw lines of $sqrt q$ for any rational $q$ units. This includes $q=2$. Of course, if you do it in real life, then it's not going to be exactly right, no measurement is. But in looking at constructions and constructible numbers, we ignore that and look at a theoretical, perfect, idealized case where these human errors aren't present. In that sense, $sqrt 2$ is absolutely drawable (when you use a construction to get a right triangle). Of course in real life imperfections arise everywhere - but mathematics is kinda beautiful in that sense, it allows us to consider the idealized situation too, as well as make it practical, give us "close enough" solutions to real life.






                share|cite|improve this answer









                $endgroup$
















                  2












                  2








                  2





                  $begingroup$

                  A lot of numbers are called "constructible", in that, if $n$ is constructible, then we can find a construction in which a line of $n$ units can be made. Granted, this is not a trivial task depending on the construction and number involved.



                  In the sense of construction and only drawing a line, then the only thing we can draw "exactly" is a line segment which we would denote as our unit, essentially $1$. Everything else requires some method of construction. We can make $2$ by appending two unit lengths; we can make $1/2$ by bisecting a unit length.



                  The only things we're given is a unit length, our straightedge, and a compass. Nothing else; take out the construction and we only have a unit. (And you could even argue drawing the line itself is a unit.) From there, we can find constructible numbers $n$, which are $n$ unit lengths long.



                  It will also be helpful to note that we cannot use rulers. I mean, they can be used, insofar as being a straightedge, but we're not allowed to use them to measure out, say, $2$ inches or whatever. This is because the ruler might be flawed, your line might be flawed - it could be too long by ever-so-many atom-widths if you want to be pedantic; what temperature it is could affect the scaling even if only minutely; blah blah blah. In constructions, we effectively view the tools and our execution of the construction as "perfect", free of human errors like these, if just in the theoretical sense.



                  Why am I rambling on about constructions?



                  Because that is at the core of why you might say you cannot draw a line of length $sqrt2$ units - because I think you're looking at the ruler. You look at it and go "I can't get to it because it's irrational. I can only guessimate in halves or quarters or whatever's on my ruler, I can only make rational estimations. I cannot find square root of $2$ just by drawing a line."



                  And you're right - you can't make $sqrt2$ just by drawing a line. You can't make anything by drawing a line, except your unit, assuming - again - the inherent perfectness of construction and technique and not knowing exact lengths a priori.



                  The only length you can draw, without other aides, is a line $1$ unit long.



                  Seems weird when you say it but that's what it comes down to.



                  So how do we draw others? We use constructions. We make use of geometric principles to demonstrate other numbers are "constructible." These numbers can be constructed, made. Given a unit, straightedge, and compass, we can make a line $n$ units long, where $n$ is constructible.



                  This gives rise to the constructible numbers. Like the real numbers, they form a field: you can multiply and add any two constructible numbers to get another one. You can also divide and subtract them.



                  What are some examples of constructible numbers? Well...




                  • All of the natural numbers (just keep appending lines of length $1$ to each)

                  • All of the rational numbers (bisections and appending of various lengths)

                  • Square roots of rational numbers (the isosceles right triangle of side length $a$ suffices to give a hypotenuse of length $sqrt a$)


                  These are not the only examples; the article I linked discusses them at further length. There are some numbers known to not be constructible:




                  • $sqrt[3]2$

                  • $sqrt pi$


                  • $cos left( arccos(x)/3 right)$ for constructible $x$ (related to how angles generally cannot be trisected)


                  I think that's enough rambling. In short:




                  • In reality, with only a straightedge, you are given a unit length, representative of $1$

                  • With compass and straightedge, you can make the constructible numbers (again, see https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Constructible_number for more info)

                  • Constructions cannot use rulers to measure out lengths: we can only have a straightedge and compass, and the former allows us a starting, unit length.

                  • In constructions, at least analyzing them in theoretical realm (rather than making practical use of them), we look at them in the sense of being "perfect" and absent of human errors. There are definitely rational approximations for $pi$ or $sqrt 2$ that are really, REALLY good (look into continued fractions if you're curious), and it shouldn't be hard to convince yourself of our ability to draw those. But constructions - if perfect, if idealized, if absent of error - also allows us to represent irrational numbers.

                  • We can draw right triangles via a construction and isosceles right triangles in particular - this isn't at all difficult - so we can draw lines of $sqrt q$ for any rational $q$ units. This includes $q=2$. Of course, if you do it in real life, then it's not going to be exactly right, no measurement is. But in looking at constructions and constructible numbers, we ignore that and look at a theoretical, perfect, idealized case where these human errors aren't present. In that sense, $sqrt 2$ is absolutely drawable (when you use a construction to get a right triangle). Of course in real life imperfections arise everywhere - but mathematics is kinda beautiful in that sense, it allows us to consider the idealized situation too, as well as make it practical, give us "close enough" solutions to real life.






                  share|cite|improve this answer









                  $endgroup$



                  A lot of numbers are called "constructible", in that, if $n$ is constructible, then we can find a construction in which a line of $n$ units can be made. Granted, this is not a trivial task depending on the construction and number involved.



                  In the sense of construction and only drawing a line, then the only thing we can draw "exactly" is a line segment which we would denote as our unit, essentially $1$. Everything else requires some method of construction. We can make $2$ by appending two unit lengths; we can make $1/2$ by bisecting a unit length.



                  The only things we're given is a unit length, our straightedge, and a compass. Nothing else; take out the construction and we only have a unit. (And you could even argue drawing the line itself is a unit.) From there, we can find constructible numbers $n$, which are $n$ unit lengths long.



                  It will also be helpful to note that we cannot use rulers. I mean, they can be used, insofar as being a straightedge, but we're not allowed to use them to measure out, say, $2$ inches or whatever. This is because the ruler might be flawed, your line might be flawed - it could be too long by ever-so-many atom-widths if you want to be pedantic; what temperature it is could affect the scaling even if only minutely; blah blah blah. In constructions, we effectively view the tools and our execution of the construction as "perfect", free of human errors like these, if just in the theoretical sense.



                  Why am I rambling on about constructions?



                  Because that is at the core of why you might say you cannot draw a line of length $sqrt2$ units - because I think you're looking at the ruler. You look at it and go "I can't get to it because it's irrational. I can only guessimate in halves or quarters or whatever's on my ruler, I can only make rational estimations. I cannot find square root of $2$ just by drawing a line."



                  And you're right - you can't make $sqrt2$ just by drawing a line. You can't make anything by drawing a line, except your unit, assuming - again - the inherent perfectness of construction and technique and not knowing exact lengths a priori.



                  The only length you can draw, without other aides, is a line $1$ unit long.



                  Seems weird when you say it but that's what it comes down to.



                  So how do we draw others? We use constructions. We make use of geometric principles to demonstrate other numbers are "constructible." These numbers can be constructed, made. Given a unit, straightedge, and compass, we can make a line $n$ units long, where $n$ is constructible.



                  This gives rise to the constructible numbers. Like the real numbers, they form a field: you can multiply and add any two constructible numbers to get another one. You can also divide and subtract them.



                  What are some examples of constructible numbers? Well...




                  • All of the natural numbers (just keep appending lines of length $1$ to each)

                  • All of the rational numbers (bisections and appending of various lengths)

                  • Square roots of rational numbers (the isosceles right triangle of side length $a$ suffices to give a hypotenuse of length $sqrt a$)


                  These are not the only examples; the article I linked discusses them at further length. There are some numbers known to not be constructible:




                  • $sqrt[3]2$

                  • $sqrt pi$


                  • $cos left( arccos(x)/3 right)$ for constructible $x$ (related to how angles generally cannot be trisected)


                  I think that's enough rambling. In short:




                  • In reality, with only a straightedge, you are given a unit length, representative of $1$

                  • With compass and straightedge, you can make the constructible numbers (again, see https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Constructible_number for more info)

                  • Constructions cannot use rulers to measure out lengths: we can only have a straightedge and compass, and the former allows us a starting, unit length.

                  • In constructions, at least analyzing them in theoretical realm (rather than making practical use of them), we look at them in the sense of being "perfect" and absent of human errors. There are definitely rational approximations for $pi$ or $sqrt 2$ that are really, REALLY good (look into continued fractions if you're curious), and it shouldn't be hard to convince yourself of our ability to draw those. But constructions - if perfect, if idealized, if absent of error - also allows us to represent irrational numbers.

                  • We can draw right triangles via a construction and isosceles right triangles in particular - this isn't at all difficult - so we can draw lines of $sqrt q$ for any rational $q$ units. This includes $q=2$. Of course, if you do it in real life, then it's not going to be exactly right, no measurement is. But in looking at constructions and constructible numbers, we ignore that and look at a theoretical, perfect, idealized case where these human errors aren't present. In that sense, $sqrt 2$ is absolutely drawable (when you use a construction to get a right triangle). Of course in real life imperfections arise everywhere - but mathematics is kinda beautiful in that sense, it allows us to consider the idealized situation too, as well as make it practical, give us "close enough" solutions to real life.







                  share|cite|improve this answer












                  share|cite|improve this answer



                  share|cite|improve this answer










                  answered Dec 16 '18 at 2:19









                  Eevee TrainerEevee Trainer

                  5,4691936




                  5,4691936






























                      draft saved

                      draft discarded




















































                      Thanks for contributing an answer to Mathematics Stack Exchange!


                      • Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!

                      But avoid



                      • Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.

                      • Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.


                      Use MathJax to format equations. MathJax reference.


                      To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.




                      draft saved


                      draft discarded














                      StackExchange.ready(
                      function () {
                      StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3042149%2fwe-cant-exactly-draw-a-line-of-length-square-root-of-2-but-can-be-constructed-u%23new-answer', 'question_page');
                      }
                      );

                      Post as a guest















                      Required, but never shown





















































                      Required, but never shown














                      Required, but never shown












                      Required, but never shown







                      Required, but never shown

































                      Required, but never shown














                      Required, but never shown












                      Required, but never shown







                      Required, but never shown







                      Popular posts from this blog

                      Bressuire

                      Cabo Verde

                      Gyllenstierna