cardinality of all real sequences












16












$begingroup$


I was wondering what the cardinality of the set of all real sequences is. A random search through this site says that it is equal to the cardinality of the real numbers. This is very surprising to me, since the cardinality of all rational sequences is the same as the cardinality of reals, and it seemed fairly intuitive to me that if cardinality of a set $A$ is strictly greater than the cardinality of the set $B$, then cardinality of $A^{mathbb{N}}$ should be strictly greater than cardinality of $B^{mathbb{N}}$. It turns out to be false.



Some technical answers have appeared in this forum elsewhere but I do not understand them. As I am not an expert in this topic, could some one explain me in simple terms why this is happening?



Also is the cardinality of all functions from reals to reals also the same as the cardinality of reals?










share|cite|improve this question









$endgroup$








  • 1




    $begingroup$
    Have you tried searching the site?
    $endgroup$
    – Asaf Karagila
    Jun 7 '13 at 14:27










  • $begingroup$
    Yes, I did and found some technical stuff too.
    $endgroup$
    – Vishal Gupta
    Jun 8 '13 at 3:44










  • $begingroup$
    @VishalGupta Can u plzz explain how |$Q^N$| =$|N|$?
    $endgroup$
    – sani
    May 12 '17 at 19:01


















16












$begingroup$


I was wondering what the cardinality of the set of all real sequences is. A random search through this site says that it is equal to the cardinality of the real numbers. This is very surprising to me, since the cardinality of all rational sequences is the same as the cardinality of reals, and it seemed fairly intuitive to me that if cardinality of a set $A$ is strictly greater than the cardinality of the set $B$, then cardinality of $A^{mathbb{N}}$ should be strictly greater than cardinality of $B^{mathbb{N}}$. It turns out to be false.



Some technical answers have appeared in this forum elsewhere but I do not understand them. As I am not an expert in this topic, could some one explain me in simple terms why this is happening?



Also is the cardinality of all functions from reals to reals also the same as the cardinality of reals?










share|cite|improve this question









$endgroup$








  • 1




    $begingroup$
    Have you tried searching the site?
    $endgroup$
    – Asaf Karagila
    Jun 7 '13 at 14:27










  • $begingroup$
    Yes, I did and found some technical stuff too.
    $endgroup$
    – Vishal Gupta
    Jun 8 '13 at 3:44










  • $begingroup$
    @VishalGupta Can u plzz explain how |$Q^N$| =$|N|$?
    $endgroup$
    – sani
    May 12 '17 at 19:01
















16












16








16


9



$begingroup$


I was wondering what the cardinality of the set of all real sequences is. A random search through this site says that it is equal to the cardinality of the real numbers. This is very surprising to me, since the cardinality of all rational sequences is the same as the cardinality of reals, and it seemed fairly intuitive to me that if cardinality of a set $A$ is strictly greater than the cardinality of the set $B$, then cardinality of $A^{mathbb{N}}$ should be strictly greater than cardinality of $B^{mathbb{N}}$. It turns out to be false.



Some technical answers have appeared in this forum elsewhere but I do not understand them. As I am not an expert in this topic, could some one explain me in simple terms why this is happening?



Also is the cardinality of all functions from reals to reals also the same as the cardinality of reals?










share|cite|improve this question









$endgroup$




I was wondering what the cardinality of the set of all real sequences is. A random search through this site says that it is equal to the cardinality of the real numbers. This is very surprising to me, since the cardinality of all rational sequences is the same as the cardinality of reals, and it seemed fairly intuitive to me that if cardinality of a set $A$ is strictly greater than the cardinality of the set $B$, then cardinality of $A^{mathbb{N}}$ should be strictly greater than cardinality of $B^{mathbb{N}}$. It turns out to be false.



Some technical answers have appeared in this forum elsewhere but I do not understand them. As I am not an expert in this topic, could some one explain me in simple terms why this is happening?



Also is the cardinality of all functions from reals to reals also the same as the cardinality of reals?







set-theory cardinals






share|cite|improve this question













share|cite|improve this question











share|cite|improve this question




share|cite|improve this question










asked Jun 7 '13 at 14:01









Vishal GuptaVishal Gupta

4,60021742




4,60021742








  • 1




    $begingroup$
    Have you tried searching the site?
    $endgroup$
    – Asaf Karagila
    Jun 7 '13 at 14:27










  • $begingroup$
    Yes, I did and found some technical stuff too.
    $endgroup$
    – Vishal Gupta
    Jun 8 '13 at 3:44










  • $begingroup$
    @VishalGupta Can u plzz explain how |$Q^N$| =$|N|$?
    $endgroup$
    – sani
    May 12 '17 at 19:01
















  • 1




    $begingroup$
    Have you tried searching the site?
    $endgroup$
    – Asaf Karagila
    Jun 7 '13 at 14:27










  • $begingroup$
    Yes, I did and found some technical stuff too.
    $endgroup$
    – Vishal Gupta
    Jun 8 '13 at 3:44










  • $begingroup$
    @VishalGupta Can u plzz explain how |$Q^N$| =$|N|$?
    $endgroup$
    – sani
    May 12 '17 at 19:01










1




1




$begingroup$
Have you tried searching the site?
$endgroup$
– Asaf Karagila
Jun 7 '13 at 14:27




$begingroup$
Have you tried searching the site?
$endgroup$
– Asaf Karagila
Jun 7 '13 at 14:27












$begingroup$
Yes, I did and found some technical stuff too.
$endgroup$
– Vishal Gupta
Jun 8 '13 at 3:44




$begingroup$
Yes, I did and found some technical stuff too.
$endgroup$
– Vishal Gupta
Jun 8 '13 at 3:44












$begingroup$
@VishalGupta Can u plzz explain how |$Q^N$| =$|N|$?
$endgroup$
– sani
May 12 '17 at 19:01






$begingroup$
@VishalGupta Can u plzz explain how |$Q^N$| =$|N|$?
$endgroup$
– sani
May 12 '17 at 19:01












5 Answers
5






active

oldest

votes


















27












$begingroup$

Identify $mathbb R$ as the set of functions $f : mathbb N to { 0,1} $.



Then any sequence ${ x_n }$ becomes a sequence ${f_n }_n$ where $f_n : mathbb N to { 0,1}$. But then, this is simply a function $g : mathbb N times mathbb N to { 0,1}$:



$$g(m,n) =f_n(m) ,.$$



This way you can construct a bijection from the sequences of real numbers to the set of functions from $mathbb N times mathbb N to { 0,1}$. Now, since $mathbb N times mathbb N$ and $mathbb N$ have the same cardinality, you get a bijection from the sequences of real numbers to the set of functions from $mathbb{N} times mathbb{N} to { 0,1}$, which is just $mathbb R$.






share|cite|improve this answer











$endgroup$













  • $begingroup$
    Thanks for the lovely answer.
    $endgroup$
    – Vishal Gupta
    Jun 8 '13 at 3:40






  • 1




    $begingroup$
    A lovely use of currying indeed.
    $endgroup$
    – Alex Vong
    Jun 6 '17 at 4:37



















6












$begingroup$

You asked for an explanation in "simple terms" why this is happening, which I take to mean an intuitive explanation instead of a formal proof, so that's what I'll give.



Focus on numbers between $0$ and $1$. Such a number is determined by a countable amount of information, namely the digits in its decimal expansion. So, a sequence of numbers between $0$ and $1$ is determined by a countable amount of countable information. But the countable union of countable sets is countable, so this countable amount of countable information can in turn be expressed by a countable amount of information, namely a countable number of digits. This can then be used to define a single real number between $0$ and $1$ which encodes the original sequence.



This idea can be used to give a formal proof. As for your question about functions, what do you know about the set of functions from $mathbb R$ to ${0,1}$?






share|cite|improve this answer









$endgroup$













  • $begingroup$
    Thanks for the very nice intuitive explanation. Yeah, I got the other question also, thanks to your hint; the cardinality is greater than equal to that of power set of real numbers. But is it equal to the cardinality of power set of real numbers?
    $endgroup$
    – Vishal Gupta
    Jun 8 '13 at 3:42






  • 1




    $begingroup$
    @Santiago Canez Can you give some intuitive idea about the converse too, that is every real sequence can be put into as numbers between 0 and 1
    $endgroup$
    – Saravanan
    Jan 20 '17 at 9:49



















5












$begingroup$

It depends on whether you are talking about finite sequences, infinite sequences, or "uncountable sequences". Here is an attempt to give you a little bit of an intuition for the mathematical territory:



If you are talking about the set of all finite real sequences, then we have the following argument: for any $n$, the cardinality of $mathbb{R}^n$ is the same as the cardinality of $mathbb{R}$ (which I will call $c$ for convenience). Thus, the set of finite sequences of a given length is a set of cardinality $c$. The cardinality of the arbitrary union of sets of cardinality $c$ gives you another set of cardinality $c$. Thus, the set of all finite sequences is of cardinality $c$. The same argument can be made regarding $mathbb{Q}$ (which has cardinality $aleph_0$)



The cardinality of infinite sequences is, however, a different story. Cantor's argument tells us that for any set $S$, we have $left| wp(S) right|>left| S right|$. For every subset of the rational numbers, there is a corresponding sequence in $mathbb{Q}^{mathbb{N}}$. Real numbers, on the other hand, are uncountable, so no infinite sequence will contain every element. So, as it ends up,
$left| mathbb{R}^{mathbb{N}} right| =left| mathbb{Q}^{mathbb{N}} right|= c$



Finally, we have the "uncountable sequences", that is, the set of functions from $mathbb{R}$ to $mathbb{R}$, which does have a greater cardinality. Here, we can use the previous argument as follows: for any subset $S subseteq mathbb{R}$, we can map $S$ to a function $f(x)$ for which $f(x)=0$ for any $xin S$. This gives us an injective map from $wp(mathbb{R})$ to the set of functions from $mathbb{R}$ to itself. Thus, the cardinality of the set of functions from $mathbb{R}$ to $mathbb{R}$ is greater than $c$.



A nice bit of cardinal arithmetic to have in your arsenal: for transfinite sets $P$ and $Q$:
$$
left| P^Qright|=max{left|Pright|,left|wp(Q)right|}
$$
EDIT: I am not sure about that last formula, let's call it a conjecture.






share|cite|improve this answer











$endgroup$













  • $begingroup$
    Thanks for the nice answer. But how did you say so, it ends up,$left| mathbb{R}^{mathbb{N}} right| =left| mathbb{Q}^{mathbb{N}} right|= c$? And could you give some reference to the last formula?
    $endgroup$
    – Vishal Gupta
    Jun 8 '13 at 3:38










  • $begingroup$
    So a little bit of elaboration on $left| mathbb{R}^{mathbb{N}} right| =left| mathbb{Q}^{mathbb{N}} right|= c$. The one on the left you know from your own research; i.e. the cardinality of the sequences of the real numbers is the same as that of the reals. The one on the right works because there's an injection from $mathbb{R}$ to $mathbb{Q}^mathbb{N}$ and another from $mathbb{Q}^mathbb{N}$ to $mathbb{R}^mathbb{N}$. I thought I had seen the last formula somewhere but now I'm not so sure.
    $endgroup$
    – Omnomnomnom
    Jun 8 '13 at 6:21










  • $begingroup$
    I think your formula holds under GCH. Specifically, $P^Q = beth_alpha^{beth_beta}$ in GCH, for some ordinals $alpha$ and $beta$. If $alpha$ has a predecessor $gamma$, then we have $P^Q = left ( 2^{beth_gamma} right )^{beth_beta} = 2^{max { beth_gamma,beth_beta }}= 2^{beth_{max { gamma,beta }}}$. Now if $P>mathcal{P}(Q)$ then $gamma geq beta$; if $P<mathcal{P}(Q)$ then $gamma<beta$; if $P=mathcal{P}(Q)$ then $gamma=beta$. In any of these cases we get what was wanted. I'm not sure what to do if $alpha$ is a limit ordinal.
    $endgroup$
    – Ian
    Sep 14 '14 at 20:25





















3












$begingroup$

In simple terms, our number-sense intuition comes from dealing with finite sets, and has very little value when dealing with infinite sets. This is why a set can have the same cardinality as a proper subset, and why $B^mathbb{N}$ can have the same cardinality as $A^mathbb{N}$ even if one is a proper subset of the other.






share|cite|improve this answer









$endgroup$













  • $begingroup$
    Thanks. But could you be a little more explanatory? Also, could you answer what is the cardinality of all real functions?
    $endgroup$
    – Vishal Gupta
    Jun 7 '13 at 14:10










  • $begingroup$
    For $A=mathbb{R}$, it turns out that $|A^mathbb{N}|=|A|$, as proved here.
    $endgroup$
    – vadim123
    Jun 7 '13 at 14:12










  • $begingroup$
    Yeah, I had seen that before posting. However, I do not understand how he got the third equality in that line.
    $endgroup$
    – Vishal Gupta
    Jun 7 '13 at 14:19










  • $begingroup$
    This comes from $aleph_0timesaleph_0=aleph_0$. See, e.g. here.
    $endgroup$
    – vadim123
    Jun 7 '13 at 16:25





















2












$begingroup$

Let $k,m$ be infinite cardinals. Then



$$(2^k)^m = 2^{k cdot m} = 2^{max { k,m }}.$$



Here I have used the axiom of choice in the second equality. The $max$ there causes the non-strict monotonicity that surprised you.






share|cite|improve this answer









$endgroup$













    Your Answer





    StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function () {
    return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function () {
    StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix) {
    StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
    });
    });
    }, "mathjax-editing");

    StackExchange.ready(function() {
    var channelOptions = {
    tags: "".split(" "),
    id: "69"
    };
    initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

    StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function() {
    // Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
    if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled) {
    StackExchange.using("snippets", function() {
    createEditor();
    });
    }
    else {
    createEditor();
    }
    });

    function createEditor() {
    StackExchange.prepareEditor({
    heartbeatType: 'answer',
    autoActivateHeartbeat: false,
    convertImagesToLinks: true,
    noModals: true,
    showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
    reputationToPostImages: 10,
    bindNavPrevention: true,
    postfix: "",
    imageUploader: {
    brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
    contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
    allowUrls: true
    },
    noCode: true, onDemand: true,
    discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
    ,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
    });


    }
    });














    draft saved

    draft discarded


















    StackExchange.ready(
    function () {
    StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f413836%2fcardinality-of-all-real-sequences%23new-answer', 'question_page');
    }
    );

    Post as a guest















    Required, but never shown

























    5 Answers
    5






    active

    oldest

    votes








    5 Answers
    5






    active

    oldest

    votes









    active

    oldest

    votes






    active

    oldest

    votes









    27












    $begingroup$

    Identify $mathbb R$ as the set of functions $f : mathbb N to { 0,1} $.



    Then any sequence ${ x_n }$ becomes a sequence ${f_n }_n$ where $f_n : mathbb N to { 0,1}$. But then, this is simply a function $g : mathbb N times mathbb N to { 0,1}$:



    $$g(m,n) =f_n(m) ,.$$



    This way you can construct a bijection from the sequences of real numbers to the set of functions from $mathbb N times mathbb N to { 0,1}$. Now, since $mathbb N times mathbb N$ and $mathbb N$ have the same cardinality, you get a bijection from the sequences of real numbers to the set of functions from $mathbb{N} times mathbb{N} to { 0,1}$, which is just $mathbb R$.






    share|cite|improve this answer











    $endgroup$













    • $begingroup$
      Thanks for the lovely answer.
      $endgroup$
      – Vishal Gupta
      Jun 8 '13 at 3:40






    • 1




      $begingroup$
      A lovely use of currying indeed.
      $endgroup$
      – Alex Vong
      Jun 6 '17 at 4:37
















    27












    $begingroup$

    Identify $mathbb R$ as the set of functions $f : mathbb N to { 0,1} $.



    Then any sequence ${ x_n }$ becomes a sequence ${f_n }_n$ where $f_n : mathbb N to { 0,1}$. But then, this is simply a function $g : mathbb N times mathbb N to { 0,1}$:



    $$g(m,n) =f_n(m) ,.$$



    This way you can construct a bijection from the sequences of real numbers to the set of functions from $mathbb N times mathbb N to { 0,1}$. Now, since $mathbb N times mathbb N$ and $mathbb N$ have the same cardinality, you get a bijection from the sequences of real numbers to the set of functions from $mathbb{N} times mathbb{N} to { 0,1}$, which is just $mathbb R$.






    share|cite|improve this answer











    $endgroup$













    • $begingroup$
      Thanks for the lovely answer.
      $endgroup$
      – Vishal Gupta
      Jun 8 '13 at 3:40






    • 1




      $begingroup$
      A lovely use of currying indeed.
      $endgroup$
      – Alex Vong
      Jun 6 '17 at 4:37














    27












    27








    27





    $begingroup$

    Identify $mathbb R$ as the set of functions $f : mathbb N to { 0,1} $.



    Then any sequence ${ x_n }$ becomes a sequence ${f_n }_n$ where $f_n : mathbb N to { 0,1}$. But then, this is simply a function $g : mathbb N times mathbb N to { 0,1}$:



    $$g(m,n) =f_n(m) ,.$$



    This way you can construct a bijection from the sequences of real numbers to the set of functions from $mathbb N times mathbb N to { 0,1}$. Now, since $mathbb N times mathbb N$ and $mathbb N$ have the same cardinality, you get a bijection from the sequences of real numbers to the set of functions from $mathbb{N} times mathbb{N} to { 0,1}$, which is just $mathbb R$.






    share|cite|improve this answer











    $endgroup$



    Identify $mathbb R$ as the set of functions $f : mathbb N to { 0,1} $.



    Then any sequence ${ x_n }$ becomes a sequence ${f_n }_n$ where $f_n : mathbb N to { 0,1}$. But then, this is simply a function $g : mathbb N times mathbb N to { 0,1}$:



    $$g(m,n) =f_n(m) ,.$$



    This way you can construct a bijection from the sequences of real numbers to the set of functions from $mathbb N times mathbb N to { 0,1}$. Now, since $mathbb N times mathbb N$ and $mathbb N$ have the same cardinality, you get a bijection from the sequences of real numbers to the set of functions from $mathbb{N} times mathbb{N} to { 0,1}$, which is just $mathbb R$.







    share|cite|improve this answer














    share|cite|improve this answer



    share|cite|improve this answer








    edited Jun 8 '13 at 3:41









    Vishal Gupta

    4,60021742




    4,60021742










    answered Jun 7 '13 at 14:58









    N. S.N. S.

    103k6111208




    103k6111208












    • $begingroup$
      Thanks for the lovely answer.
      $endgroup$
      – Vishal Gupta
      Jun 8 '13 at 3:40






    • 1




      $begingroup$
      A lovely use of currying indeed.
      $endgroup$
      – Alex Vong
      Jun 6 '17 at 4:37


















    • $begingroup$
      Thanks for the lovely answer.
      $endgroup$
      – Vishal Gupta
      Jun 8 '13 at 3:40






    • 1




      $begingroup$
      A lovely use of currying indeed.
      $endgroup$
      – Alex Vong
      Jun 6 '17 at 4:37
















    $begingroup$
    Thanks for the lovely answer.
    $endgroup$
    – Vishal Gupta
    Jun 8 '13 at 3:40




    $begingroup$
    Thanks for the lovely answer.
    $endgroup$
    – Vishal Gupta
    Jun 8 '13 at 3:40




    1




    1




    $begingroup$
    A lovely use of currying indeed.
    $endgroup$
    – Alex Vong
    Jun 6 '17 at 4:37




    $begingroup$
    A lovely use of currying indeed.
    $endgroup$
    – Alex Vong
    Jun 6 '17 at 4:37











    6












    $begingroup$

    You asked for an explanation in "simple terms" why this is happening, which I take to mean an intuitive explanation instead of a formal proof, so that's what I'll give.



    Focus on numbers between $0$ and $1$. Such a number is determined by a countable amount of information, namely the digits in its decimal expansion. So, a sequence of numbers between $0$ and $1$ is determined by a countable amount of countable information. But the countable union of countable sets is countable, so this countable amount of countable information can in turn be expressed by a countable amount of information, namely a countable number of digits. This can then be used to define a single real number between $0$ and $1$ which encodes the original sequence.



    This idea can be used to give a formal proof. As for your question about functions, what do you know about the set of functions from $mathbb R$ to ${0,1}$?






    share|cite|improve this answer









    $endgroup$













    • $begingroup$
      Thanks for the very nice intuitive explanation. Yeah, I got the other question also, thanks to your hint; the cardinality is greater than equal to that of power set of real numbers. But is it equal to the cardinality of power set of real numbers?
      $endgroup$
      – Vishal Gupta
      Jun 8 '13 at 3:42






    • 1




      $begingroup$
      @Santiago Canez Can you give some intuitive idea about the converse too, that is every real sequence can be put into as numbers between 0 and 1
      $endgroup$
      – Saravanan
      Jan 20 '17 at 9:49
















    6












    $begingroup$

    You asked for an explanation in "simple terms" why this is happening, which I take to mean an intuitive explanation instead of a formal proof, so that's what I'll give.



    Focus on numbers between $0$ and $1$. Such a number is determined by a countable amount of information, namely the digits in its decimal expansion. So, a sequence of numbers between $0$ and $1$ is determined by a countable amount of countable information. But the countable union of countable sets is countable, so this countable amount of countable information can in turn be expressed by a countable amount of information, namely a countable number of digits. This can then be used to define a single real number between $0$ and $1$ which encodes the original sequence.



    This idea can be used to give a formal proof. As for your question about functions, what do you know about the set of functions from $mathbb R$ to ${0,1}$?






    share|cite|improve this answer









    $endgroup$













    • $begingroup$
      Thanks for the very nice intuitive explanation. Yeah, I got the other question also, thanks to your hint; the cardinality is greater than equal to that of power set of real numbers. But is it equal to the cardinality of power set of real numbers?
      $endgroup$
      – Vishal Gupta
      Jun 8 '13 at 3:42






    • 1




      $begingroup$
      @Santiago Canez Can you give some intuitive idea about the converse too, that is every real sequence can be put into as numbers between 0 and 1
      $endgroup$
      – Saravanan
      Jan 20 '17 at 9:49














    6












    6








    6





    $begingroup$

    You asked for an explanation in "simple terms" why this is happening, which I take to mean an intuitive explanation instead of a formal proof, so that's what I'll give.



    Focus on numbers between $0$ and $1$. Such a number is determined by a countable amount of information, namely the digits in its decimal expansion. So, a sequence of numbers between $0$ and $1$ is determined by a countable amount of countable information. But the countable union of countable sets is countable, so this countable amount of countable information can in turn be expressed by a countable amount of information, namely a countable number of digits. This can then be used to define a single real number between $0$ and $1$ which encodes the original sequence.



    This idea can be used to give a formal proof. As for your question about functions, what do you know about the set of functions from $mathbb R$ to ${0,1}$?






    share|cite|improve this answer









    $endgroup$



    You asked for an explanation in "simple terms" why this is happening, which I take to mean an intuitive explanation instead of a formal proof, so that's what I'll give.



    Focus on numbers between $0$ and $1$. Such a number is determined by a countable amount of information, namely the digits in its decimal expansion. So, a sequence of numbers between $0$ and $1$ is determined by a countable amount of countable information. But the countable union of countable sets is countable, so this countable amount of countable information can in turn be expressed by a countable amount of information, namely a countable number of digits. This can then be used to define a single real number between $0$ and $1$ which encodes the original sequence.



    This idea can be used to give a formal proof. As for your question about functions, what do you know about the set of functions from $mathbb R$ to ${0,1}$?







    share|cite|improve this answer












    share|cite|improve this answer



    share|cite|improve this answer










    answered Jun 7 '13 at 14:39









    Santiago CanezSantiago Canez

    2,06111113




    2,06111113












    • $begingroup$
      Thanks for the very nice intuitive explanation. Yeah, I got the other question also, thanks to your hint; the cardinality is greater than equal to that of power set of real numbers. But is it equal to the cardinality of power set of real numbers?
      $endgroup$
      – Vishal Gupta
      Jun 8 '13 at 3:42






    • 1




      $begingroup$
      @Santiago Canez Can you give some intuitive idea about the converse too, that is every real sequence can be put into as numbers between 0 and 1
      $endgroup$
      – Saravanan
      Jan 20 '17 at 9:49


















    • $begingroup$
      Thanks for the very nice intuitive explanation. Yeah, I got the other question also, thanks to your hint; the cardinality is greater than equal to that of power set of real numbers. But is it equal to the cardinality of power set of real numbers?
      $endgroup$
      – Vishal Gupta
      Jun 8 '13 at 3:42






    • 1




      $begingroup$
      @Santiago Canez Can you give some intuitive idea about the converse too, that is every real sequence can be put into as numbers between 0 and 1
      $endgroup$
      – Saravanan
      Jan 20 '17 at 9:49
















    $begingroup$
    Thanks for the very nice intuitive explanation. Yeah, I got the other question also, thanks to your hint; the cardinality is greater than equal to that of power set of real numbers. But is it equal to the cardinality of power set of real numbers?
    $endgroup$
    – Vishal Gupta
    Jun 8 '13 at 3:42




    $begingroup$
    Thanks for the very nice intuitive explanation. Yeah, I got the other question also, thanks to your hint; the cardinality is greater than equal to that of power set of real numbers. But is it equal to the cardinality of power set of real numbers?
    $endgroup$
    – Vishal Gupta
    Jun 8 '13 at 3:42




    1




    1




    $begingroup$
    @Santiago Canez Can you give some intuitive idea about the converse too, that is every real sequence can be put into as numbers between 0 and 1
    $endgroup$
    – Saravanan
    Jan 20 '17 at 9:49




    $begingroup$
    @Santiago Canez Can you give some intuitive idea about the converse too, that is every real sequence can be put into as numbers between 0 and 1
    $endgroup$
    – Saravanan
    Jan 20 '17 at 9:49











    5












    $begingroup$

    It depends on whether you are talking about finite sequences, infinite sequences, or "uncountable sequences". Here is an attempt to give you a little bit of an intuition for the mathematical territory:



    If you are talking about the set of all finite real sequences, then we have the following argument: for any $n$, the cardinality of $mathbb{R}^n$ is the same as the cardinality of $mathbb{R}$ (which I will call $c$ for convenience). Thus, the set of finite sequences of a given length is a set of cardinality $c$. The cardinality of the arbitrary union of sets of cardinality $c$ gives you another set of cardinality $c$. Thus, the set of all finite sequences is of cardinality $c$. The same argument can be made regarding $mathbb{Q}$ (which has cardinality $aleph_0$)



    The cardinality of infinite sequences is, however, a different story. Cantor's argument tells us that for any set $S$, we have $left| wp(S) right|>left| S right|$. For every subset of the rational numbers, there is a corresponding sequence in $mathbb{Q}^{mathbb{N}}$. Real numbers, on the other hand, are uncountable, so no infinite sequence will contain every element. So, as it ends up,
    $left| mathbb{R}^{mathbb{N}} right| =left| mathbb{Q}^{mathbb{N}} right|= c$



    Finally, we have the "uncountable sequences", that is, the set of functions from $mathbb{R}$ to $mathbb{R}$, which does have a greater cardinality. Here, we can use the previous argument as follows: for any subset $S subseteq mathbb{R}$, we can map $S$ to a function $f(x)$ for which $f(x)=0$ for any $xin S$. This gives us an injective map from $wp(mathbb{R})$ to the set of functions from $mathbb{R}$ to itself. Thus, the cardinality of the set of functions from $mathbb{R}$ to $mathbb{R}$ is greater than $c$.



    A nice bit of cardinal arithmetic to have in your arsenal: for transfinite sets $P$ and $Q$:
    $$
    left| P^Qright|=max{left|Pright|,left|wp(Q)right|}
    $$
    EDIT: I am not sure about that last formula, let's call it a conjecture.






    share|cite|improve this answer











    $endgroup$













    • $begingroup$
      Thanks for the nice answer. But how did you say so, it ends up,$left| mathbb{R}^{mathbb{N}} right| =left| mathbb{Q}^{mathbb{N}} right|= c$? And could you give some reference to the last formula?
      $endgroup$
      – Vishal Gupta
      Jun 8 '13 at 3:38










    • $begingroup$
      So a little bit of elaboration on $left| mathbb{R}^{mathbb{N}} right| =left| mathbb{Q}^{mathbb{N}} right|= c$. The one on the left you know from your own research; i.e. the cardinality of the sequences of the real numbers is the same as that of the reals. The one on the right works because there's an injection from $mathbb{R}$ to $mathbb{Q}^mathbb{N}$ and another from $mathbb{Q}^mathbb{N}$ to $mathbb{R}^mathbb{N}$. I thought I had seen the last formula somewhere but now I'm not so sure.
      $endgroup$
      – Omnomnomnom
      Jun 8 '13 at 6:21










    • $begingroup$
      I think your formula holds under GCH. Specifically, $P^Q = beth_alpha^{beth_beta}$ in GCH, for some ordinals $alpha$ and $beta$. If $alpha$ has a predecessor $gamma$, then we have $P^Q = left ( 2^{beth_gamma} right )^{beth_beta} = 2^{max { beth_gamma,beth_beta }}= 2^{beth_{max { gamma,beta }}}$. Now if $P>mathcal{P}(Q)$ then $gamma geq beta$; if $P<mathcal{P}(Q)$ then $gamma<beta$; if $P=mathcal{P}(Q)$ then $gamma=beta$. In any of these cases we get what was wanted. I'm not sure what to do if $alpha$ is a limit ordinal.
      $endgroup$
      – Ian
      Sep 14 '14 at 20:25


















    5












    $begingroup$

    It depends on whether you are talking about finite sequences, infinite sequences, or "uncountable sequences". Here is an attempt to give you a little bit of an intuition for the mathematical territory:



    If you are talking about the set of all finite real sequences, then we have the following argument: for any $n$, the cardinality of $mathbb{R}^n$ is the same as the cardinality of $mathbb{R}$ (which I will call $c$ for convenience). Thus, the set of finite sequences of a given length is a set of cardinality $c$. The cardinality of the arbitrary union of sets of cardinality $c$ gives you another set of cardinality $c$. Thus, the set of all finite sequences is of cardinality $c$. The same argument can be made regarding $mathbb{Q}$ (which has cardinality $aleph_0$)



    The cardinality of infinite sequences is, however, a different story. Cantor's argument tells us that for any set $S$, we have $left| wp(S) right|>left| S right|$. For every subset of the rational numbers, there is a corresponding sequence in $mathbb{Q}^{mathbb{N}}$. Real numbers, on the other hand, are uncountable, so no infinite sequence will contain every element. So, as it ends up,
    $left| mathbb{R}^{mathbb{N}} right| =left| mathbb{Q}^{mathbb{N}} right|= c$



    Finally, we have the "uncountable sequences", that is, the set of functions from $mathbb{R}$ to $mathbb{R}$, which does have a greater cardinality. Here, we can use the previous argument as follows: for any subset $S subseteq mathbb{R}$, we can map $S$ to a function $f(x)$ for which $f(x)=0$ for any $xin S$. This gives us an injective map from $wp(mathbb{R})$ to the set of functions from $mathbb{R}$ to itself. Thus, the cardinality of the set of functions from $mathbb{R}$ to $mathbb{R}$ is greater than $c$.



    A nice bit of cardinal arithmetic to have in your arsenal: for transfinite sets $P$ and $Q$:
    $$
    left| P^Qright|=max{left|Pright|,left|wp(Q)right|}
    $$
    EDIT: I am not sure about that last formula, let's call it a conjecture.






    share|cite|improve this answer











    $endgroup$













    • $begingroup$
      Thanks for the nice answer. But how did you say so, it ends up,$left| mathbb{R}^{mathbb{N}} right| =left| mathbb{Q}^{mathbb{N}} right|= c$? And could you give some reference to the last formula?
      $endgroup$
      – Vishal Gupta
      Jun 8 '13 at 3:38










    • $begingroup$
      So a little bit of elaboration on $left| mathbb{R}^{mathbb{N}} right| =left| mathbb{Q}^{mathbb{N}} right|= c$. The one on the left you know from your own research; i.e. the cardinality of the sequences of the real numbers is the same as that of the reals. The one on the right works because there's an injection from $mathbb{R}$ to $mathbb{Q}^mathbb{N}$ and another from $mathbb{Q}^mathbb{N}$ to $mathbb{R}^mathbb{N}$. I thought I had seen the last formula somewhere but now I'm not so sure.
      $endgroup$
      – Omnomnomnom
      Jun 8 '13 at 6:21










    • $begingroup$
      I think your formula holds under GCH. Specifically, $P^Q = beth_alpha^{beth_beta}$ in GCH, for some ordinals $alpha$ and $beta$. If $alpha$ has a predecessor $gamma$, then we have $P^Q = left ( 2^{beth_gamma} right )^{beth_beta} = 2^{max { beth_gamma,beth_beta }}= 2^{beth_{max { gamma,beta }}}$. Now if $P>mathcal{P}(Q)$ then $gamma geq beta$; if $P<mathcal{P}(Q)$ then $gamma<beta$; if $P=mathcal{P}(Q)$ then $gamma=beta$. In any of these cases we get what was wanted. I'm not sure what to do if $alpha$ is a limit ordinal.
      $endgroup$
      – Ian
      Sep 14 '14 at 20:25
















    5












    5








    5





    $begingroup$

    It depends on whether you are talking about finite sequences, infinite sequences, or "uncountable sequences". Here is an attempt to give you a little bit of an intuition for the mathematical territory:



    If you are talking about the set of all finite real sequences, then we have the following argument: for any $n$, the cardinality of $mathbb{R}^n$ is the same as the cardinality of $mathbb{R}$ (which I will call $c$ for convenience). Thus, the set of finite sequences of a given length is a set of cardinality $c$. The cardinality of the arbitrary union of sets of cardinality $c$ gives you another set of cardinality $c$. Thus, the set of all finite sequences is of cardinality $c$. The same argument can be made regarding $mathbb{Q}$ (which has cardinality $aleph_0$)



    The cardinality of infinite sequences is, however, a different story. Cantor's argument tells us that for any set $S$, we have $left| wp(S) right|>left| S right|$. For every subset of the rational numbers, there is a corresponding sequence in $mathbb{Q}^{mathbb{N}}$. Real numbers, on the other hand, are uncountable, so no infinite sequence will contain every element. So, as it ends up,
    $left| mathbb{R}^{mathbb{N}} right| =left| mathbb{Q}^{mathbb{N}} right|= c$



    Finally, we have the "uncountable sequences", that is, the set of functions from $mathbb{R}$ to $mathbb{R}$, which does have a greater cardinality. Here, we can use the previous argument as follows: for any subset $S subseteq mathbb{R}$, we can map $S$ to a function $f(x)$ for which $f(x)=0$ for any $xin S$. This gives us an injective map from $wp(mathbb{R})$ to the set of functions from $mathbb{R}$ to itself. Thus, the cardinality of the set of functions from $mathbb{R}$ to $mathbb{R}$ is greater than $c$.



    A nice bit of cardinal arithmetic to have in your arsenal: for transfinite sets $P$ and $Q$:
    $$
    left| P^Qright|=max{left|Pright|,left|wp(Q)right|}
    $$
    EDIT: I am not sure about that last formula, let's call it a conjecture.






    share|cite|improve this answer











    $endgroup$



    It depends on whether you are talking about finite sequences, infinite sequences, or "uncountable sequences". Here is an attempt to give you a little bit of an intuition for the mathematical territory:



    If you are talking about the set of all finite real sequences, then we have the following argument: for any $n$, the cardinality of $mathbb{R}^n$ is the same as the cardinality of $mathbb{R}$ (which I will call $c$ for convenience). Thus, the set of finite sequences of a given length is a set of cardinality $c$. The cardinality of the arbitrary union of sets of cardinality $c$ gives you another set of cardinality $c$. Thus, the set of all finite sequences is of cardinality $c$. The same argument can be made regarding $mathbb{Q}$ (which has cardinality $aleph_0$)



    The cardinality of infinite sequences is, however, a different story. Cantor's argument tells us that for any set $S$, we have $left| wp(S) right|>left| S right|$. For every subset of the rational numbers, there is a corresponding sequence in $mathbb{Q}^{mathbb{N}}$. Real numbers, on the other hand, are uncountable, so no infinite sequence will contain every element. So, as it ends up,
    $left| mathbb{R}^{mathbb{N}} right| =left| mathbb{Q}^{mathbb{N}} right|= c$



    Finally, we have the "uncountable sequences", that is, the set of functions from $mathbb{R}$ to $mathbb{R}$, which does have a greater cardinality. Here, we can use the previous argument as follows: for any subset $S subseteq mathbb{R}$, we can map $S$ to a function $f(x)$ for which $f(x)=0$ for any $xin S$. This gives us an injective map from $wp(mathbb{R})$ to the set of functions from $mathbb{R}$ to itself. Thus, the cardinality of the set of functions from $mathbb{R}$ to $mathbb{R}$ is greater than $c$.



    A nice bit of cardinal arithmetic to have in your arsenal: for transfinite sets $P$ and $Q$:
    $$
    left| P^Qright|=max{left|Pright|,left|wp(Q)right|}
    $$
    EDIT: I am not sure about that last formula, let's call it a conjecture.







    share|cite|improve this answer














    share|cite|improve this answer



    share|cite|improve this answer








    edited Jun 8 '13 at 6:15

























    answered Jun 7 '13 at 14:42









    OmnomnomnomOmnomnomnom

    127k790178




    127k790178












    • $begingroup$
      Thanks for the nice answer. But how did you say so, it ends up,$left| mathbb{R}^{mathbb{N}} right| =left| mathbb{Q}^{mathbb{N}} right|= c$? And could you give some reference to the last formula?
      $endgroup$
      – Vishal Gupta
      Jun 8 '13 at 3:38










    • $begingroup$
      So a little bit of elaboration on $left| mathbb{R}^{mathbb{N}} right| =left| mathbb{Q}^{mathbb{N}} right|= c$. The one on the left you know from your own research; i.e. the cardinality of the sequences of the real numbers is the same as that of the reals. The one on the right works because there's an injection from $mathbb{R}$ to $mathbb{Q}^mathbb{N}$ and another from $mathbb{Q}^mathbb{N}$ to $mathbb{R}^mathbb{N}$. I thought I had seen the last formula somewhere but now I'm not so sure.
      $endgroup$
      – Omnomnomnom
      Jun 8 '13 at 6:21










    • $begingroup$
      I think your formula holds under GCH. Specifically, $P^Q = beth_alpha^{beth_beta}$ in GCH, for some ordinals $alpha$ and $beta$. If $alpha$ has a predecessor $gamma$, then we have $P^Q = left ( 2^{beth_gamma} right )^{beth_beta} = 2^{max { beth_gamma,beth_beta }}= 2^{beth_{max { gamma,beta }}}$. Now if $P>mathcal{P}(Q)$ then $gamma geq beta$; if $P<mathcal{P}(Q)$ then $gamma<beta$; if $P=mathcal{P}(Q)$ then $gamma=beta$. In any of these cases we get what was wanted. I'm not sure what to do if $alpha$ is a limit ordinal.
      $endgroup$
      – Ian
      Sep 14 '14 at 20:25




















    • $begingroup$
      Thanks for the nice answer. But how did you say so, it ends up,$left| mathbb{R}^{mathbb{N}} right| =left| mathbb{Q}^{mathbb{N}} right|= c$? And could you give some reference to the last formula?
      $endgroup$
      – Vishal Gupta
      Jun 8 '13 at 3:38










    • $begingroup$
      So a little bit of elaboration on $left| mathbb{R}^{mathbb{N}} right| =left| mathbb{Q}^{mathbb{N}} right|= c$. The one on the left you know from your own research; i.e. the cardinality of the sequences of the real numbers is the same as that of the reals. The one on the right works because there's an injection from $mathbb{R}$ to $mathbb{Q}^mathbb{N}$ and another from $mathbb{Q}^mathbb{N}$ to $mathbb{R}^mathbb{N}$. I thought I had seen the last formula somewhere but now I'm not so sure.
      $endgroup$
      – Omnomnomnom
      Jun 8 '13 at 6:21










    • $begingroup$
      I think your formula holds under GCH. Specifically, $P^Q = beth_alpha^{beth_beta}$ in GCH, for some ordinals $alpha$ and $beta$. If $alpha$ has a predecessor $gamma$, then we have $P^Q = left ( 2^{beth_gamma} right )^{beth_beta} = 2^{max { beth_gamma,beth_beta }}= 2^{beth_{max { gamma,beta }}}$. Now if $P>mathcal{P}(Q)$ then $gamma geq beta$; if $P<mathcal{P}(Q)$ then $gamma<beta$; if $P=mathcal{P}(Q)$ then $gamma=beta$. In any of these cases we get what was wanted. I'm not sure what to do if $alpha$ is a limit ordinal.
      $endgroup$
      – Ian
      Sep 14 '14 at 20:25


















    $begingroup$
    Thanks for the nice answer. But how did you say so, it ends up,$left| mathbb{R}^{mathbb{N}} right| =left| mathbb{Q}^{mathbb{N}} right|= c$? And could you give some reference to the last formula?
    $endgroup$
    – Vishal Gupta
    Jun 8 '13 at 3:38




    $begingroup$
    Thanks for the nice answer. But how did you say so, it ends up,$left| mathbb{R}^{mathbb{N}} right| =left| mathbb{Q}^{mathbb{N}} right|= c$? And could you give some reference to the last formula?
    $endgroup$
    – Vishal Gupta
    Jun 8 '13 at 3:38












    $begingroup$
    So a little bit of elaboration on $left| mathbb{R}^{mathbb{N}} right| =left| mathbb{Q}^{mathbb{N}} right|= c$. The one on the left you know from your own research; i.e. the cardinality of the sequences of the real numbers is the same as that of the reals. The one on the right works because there's an injection from $mathbb{R}$ to $mathbb{Q}^mathbb{N}$ and another from $mathbb{Q}^mathbb{N}$ to $mathbb{R}^mathbb{N}$. I thought I had seen the last formula somewhere but now I'm not so sure.
    $endgroup$
    – Omnomnomnom
    Jun 8 '13 at 6:21




    $begingroup$
    So a little bit of elaboration on $left| mathbb{R}^{mathbb{N}} right| =left| mathbb{Q}^{mathbb{N}} right|= c$. The one on the left you know from your own research; i.e. the cardinality of the sequences of the real numbers is the same as that of the reals. The one on the right works because there's an injection from $mathbb{R}$ to $mathbb{Q}^mathbb{N}$ and another from $mathbb{Q}^mathbb{N}$ to $mathbb{R}^mathbb{N}$. I thought I had seen the last formula somewhere but now I'm not so sure.
    $endgroup$
    – Omnomnomnom
    Jun 8 '13 at 6:21












    $begingroup$
    I think your formula holds under GCH. Specifically, $P^Q = beth_alpha^{beth_beta}$ in GCH, for some ordinals $alpha$ and $beta$. If $alpha$ has a predecessor $gamma$, then we have $P^Q = left ( 2^{beth_gamma} right )^{beth_beta} = 2^{max { beth_gamma,beth_beta }}= 2^{beth_{max { gamma,beta }}}$. Now if $P>mathcal{P}(Q)$ then $gamma geq beta$; if $P<mathcal{P}(Q)$ then $gamma<beta$; if $P=mathcal{P}(Q)$ then $gamma=beta$. In any of these cases we get what was wanted. I'm not sure what to do if $alpha$ is a limit ordinal.
    $endgroup$
    – Ian
    Sep 14 '14 at 20:25






    $begingroup$
    I think your formula holds under GCH. Specifically, $P^Q = beth_alpha^{beth_beta}$ in GCH, for some ordinals $alpha$ and $beta$. If $alpha$ has a predecessor $gamma$, then we have $P^Q = left ( 2^{beth_gamma} right )^{beth_beta} = 2^{max { beth_gamma,beth_beta }}= 2^{beth_{max { gamma,beta }}}$. Now if $P>mathcal{P}(Q)$ then $gamma geq beta$; if $P<mathcal{P}(Q)$ then $gamma<beta$; if $P=mathcal{P}(Q)$ then $gamma=beta$. In any of these cases we get what was wanted. I'm not sure what to do if $alpha$ is a limit ordinal.
    $endgroup$
    – Ian
    Sep 14 '14 at 20:25













    3












    $begingroup$

    In simple terms, our number-sense intuition comes from dealing with finite sets, and has very little value when dealing with infinite sets. This is why a set can have the same cardinality as a proper subset, and why $B^mathbb{N}$ can have the same cardinality as $A^mathbb{N}$ even if one is a proper subset of the other.






    share|cite|improve this answer









    $endgroup$













    • $begingroup$
      Thanks. But could you be a little more explanatory? Also, could you answer what is the cardinality of all real functions?
      $endgroup$
      – Vishal Gupta
      Jun 7 '13 at 14:10










    • $begingroup$
      For $A=mathbb{R}$, it turns out that $|A^mathbb{N}|=|A|$, as proved here.
      $endgroup$
      – vadim123
      Jun 7 '13 at 14:12










    • $begingroup$
      Yeah, I had seen that before posting. However, I do not understand how he got the third equality in that line.
      $endgroup$
      – Vishal Gupta
      Jun 7 '13 at 14:19










    • $begingroup$
      This comes from $aleph_0timesaleph_0=aleph_0$. See, e.g. here.
      $endgroup$
      – vadim123
      Jun 7 '13 at 16:25


















    3












    $begingroup$

    In simple terms, our number-sense intuition comes from dealing with finite sets, and has very little value when dealing with infinite sets. This is why a set can have the same cardinality as a proper subset, and why $B^mathbb{N}$ can have the same cardinality as $A^mathbb{N}$ even if one is a proper subset of the other.






    share|cite|improve this answer









    $endgroup$













    • $begingroup$
      Thanks. But could you be a little more explanatory? Also, could you answer what is the cardinality of all real functions?
      $endgroup$
      – Vishal Gupta
      Jun 7 '13 at 14:10










    • $begingroup$
      For $A=mathbb{R}$, it turns out that $|A^mathbb{N}|=|A|$, as proved here.
      $endgroup$
      – vadim123
      Jun 7 '13 at 14:12










    • $begingroup$
      Yeah, I had seen that before posting. However, I do not understand how he got the third equality in that line.
      $endgroup$
      – Vishal Gupta
      Jun 7 '13 at 14:19










    • $begingroup$
      This comes from $aleph_0timesaleph_0=aleph_0$. See, e.g. here.
      $endgroup$
      – vadim123
      Jun 7 '13 at 16:25
















    3












    3








    3





    $begingroup$

    In simple terms, our number-sense intuition comes from dealing with finite sets, and has very little value when dealing with infinite sets. This is why a set can have the same cardinality as a proper subset, and why $B^mathbb{N}$ can have the same cardinality as $A^mathbb{N}$ even if one is a proper subset of the other.






    share|cite|improve this answer









    $endgroup$



    In simple terms, our number-sense intuition comes from dealing with finite sets, and has very little value when dealing with infinite sets. This is why a set can have the same cardinality as a proper subset, and why $B^mathbb{N}$ can have the same cardinality as $A^mathbb{N}$ even if one is a proper subset of the other.







    share|cite|improve this answer












    share|cite|improve this answer



    share|cite|improve this answer










    answered Jun 7 '13 at 14:08









    vadim123vadim123

    75.9k897189




    75.9k897189












    • $begingroup$
      Thanks. But could you be a little more explanatory? Also, could you answer what is the cardinality of all real functions?
      $endgroup$
      – Vishal Gupta
      Jun 7 '13 at 14:10










    • $begingroup$
      For $A=mathbb{R}$, it turns out that $|A^mathbb{N}|=|A|$, as proved here.
      $endgroup$
      – vadim123
      Jun 7 '13 at 14:12










    • $begingroup$
      Yeah, I had seen that before posting. However, I do not understand how he got the third equality in that line.
      $endgroup$
      – Vishal Gupta
      Jun 7 '13 at 14:19










    • $begingroup$
      This comes from $aleph_0timesaleph_0=aleph_0$. See, e.g. here.
      $endgroup$
      – vadim123
      Jun 7 '13 at 16:25




















    • $begingroup$
      Thanks. But could you be a little more explanatory? Also, could you answer what is the cardinality of all real functions?
      $endgroup$
      – Vishal Gupta
      Jun 7 '13 at 14:10










    • $begingroup$
      For $A=mathbb{R}$, it turns out that $|A^mathbb{N}|=|A|$, as proved here.
      $endgroup$
      – vadim123
      Jun 7 '13 at 14:12










    • $begingroup$
      Yeah, I had seen that before posting. However, I do not understand how he got the third equality in that line.
      $endgroup$
      – Vishal Gupta
      Jun 7 '13 at 14:19










    • $begingroup$
      This comes from $aleph_0timesaleph_0=aleph_0$. See, e.g. here.
      $endgroup$
      – vadim123
      Jun 7 '13 at 16:25


















    $begingroup$
    Thanks. But could you be a little more explanatory? Also, could you answer what is the cardinality of all real functions?
    $endgroup$
    – Vishal Gupta
    Jun 7 '13 at 14:10




    $begingroup$
    Thanks. But could you be a little more explanatory? Also, could you answer what is the cardinality of all real functions?
    $endgroup$
    – Vishal Gupta
    Jun 7 '13 at 14:10












    $begingroup$
    For $A=mathbb{R}$, it turns out that $|A^mathbb{N}|=|A|$, as proved here.
    $endgroup$
    – vadim123
    Jun 7 '13 at 14:12




    $begingroup$
    For $A=mathbb{R}$, it turns out that $|A^mathbb{N}|=|A|$, as proved here.
    $endgroup$
    – vadim123
    Jun 7 '13 at 14:12












    $begingroup$
    Yeah, I had seen that before posting. However, I do not understand how he got the third equality in that line.
    $endgroup$
    – Vishal Gupta
    Jun 7 '13 at 14:19




    $begingroup$
    Yeah, I had seen that before posting. However, I do not understand how he got the third equality in that line.
    $endgroup$
    – Vishal Gupta
    Jun 7 '13 at 14:19












    $begingroup$
    This comes from $aleph_0timesaleph_0=aleph_0$. See, e.g. here.
    $endgroup$
    – vadim123
    Jun 7 '13 at 16:25






    $begingroup$
    This comes from $aleph_0timesaleph_0=aleph_0$. See, e.g. here.
    $endgroup$
    – vadim123
    Jun 7 '13 at 16:25













    2












    $begingroup$

    Let $k,m$ be infinite cardinals. Then



    $$(2^k)^m = 2^{k cdot m} = 2^{max { k,m }}.$$



    Here I have used the axiom of choice in the second equality. The $max$ there causes the non-strict monotonicity that surprised you.






    share|cite|improve this answer









    $endgroup$


















      2












      $begingroup$

      Let $k,m$ be infinite cardinals. Then



      $$(2^k)^m = 2^{k cdot m} = 2^{max { k,m }}.$$



      Here I have used the axiom of choice in the second equality. The $max$ there causes the non-strict monotonicity that surprised you.






      share|cite|improve this answer









      $endgroup$
















        2












        2








        2





        $begingroup$

        Let $k,m$ be infinite cardinals. Then



        $$(2^k)^m = 2^{k cdot m} = 2^{max { k,m }}.$$



        Here I have used the axiom of choice in the second equality. The $max$ there causes the non-strict monotonicity that surprised you.






        share|cite|improve this answer









        $endgroup$



        Let $k,m$ be infinite cardinals. Then



        $$(2^k)^m = 2^{k cdot m} = 2^{max { k,m }}.$$



        Here I have used the axiom of choice in the second equality. The $max$ there causes the non-strict monotonicity that surprised you.







        share|cite|improve this answer












        share|cite|improve this answer



        share|cite|improve this answer










        answered Sep 14 '14 at 20:08









        IanIan

        67.8k25388




        67.8k25388






























            draft saved

            draft discarded




















































            Thanks for contributing an answer to Mathematics Stack Exchange!


            • Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!

            But avoid



            • Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.

            • Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.


            Use MathJax to format equations. MathJax reference.


            To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.




            draft saved


            draft discarded














            StackExchange.ready(
            function () {
            StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f413836%2fcardinality-of-all-real-sequences%23new-answer', 'question_page');
            }
            );

            Post as a guest















            Required, but never shown





















































            Required, but never shown














            Required, but never shown












            Required, but never shown







            Required, but never shown

































            Required, but never shown














            Required, but never shown












            Required, but never shown







            Required, but never shown







            Popular posts from this blog

            Bressuire

            Cabo Verde

            Gyllenstierna