cardinality of all real sequences
$begingroup$
I was wondering what the cardinality of the set of all real sequences is. A random search through this site says that it is equal to the cardinality of the real numbers. This is very surprising to me, since the cardinality of all rational sequences is the same as the cardinality of reals, and it seemed fairly intuitive to me that if cardinality of a set $A$ is strictly greater than the cardinality of the set $B$, then cardinality of $A^{mathbb{N}}$ should be strictly greater than cardinality of $B^{mathbb{N}}$. It turns out to be false.
Some technical answers have appeared in this forum elsewhere but I do not understand them. As I am not an expert in this topic, could some one explain me in simple terms why this is happening?
Also is the cardinality of all functions from reals to reals also the same as the cardinality of reals?
set-theory cardinals
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
I was wondering what the cardinality of the set of all real sequences is. A random search through this site says that it is equal to the cardinality of the real numbers. This is very surprising to me, since the cardinality of all rational sequences is the same as the cardinality of reals, and it seemed fairly intuitive to me that if cardinality of a set $A$ is strictly greater than the cardinality of the set $B$, then cardinality of $A^{mathbb{N}}$ should be strictly greater than cardinality of $B^{mathbb{N}}$. It turns out to be false.
Some technical answers have appeared in this forum elsewhere but I do not understand them. As I am not an expert in this topic, could some one explain me in simple terms why this is happening?
Also is the cardinality of all functions from reals to reals also the same as the cardinality of reals?
set-theory cardinals
$endgroup$
1
$begingroup$
Have you tried searching the site?
$endgroup$
– Asaf Karagila♦
Jun 7 '13 at 14:27
$begingroup$
Yes, I did and found some technical stuff too.
$endgroup$
– Vishal Gupta
Jun 8 '13 at 3:44
$begingroup$
@VishalGupta Can u plzz explain how |$Q^N$| =$|N|$?
$endgroup$
– sani
May 12 '17 at 19:01
add a comment |
$begingroup$
I was wondering what the cardinality of the set of all real sequences is. A random search through this site says that it is equal to the cardinality of the real numbers. This is very surprising to me, since the cardinality of all rational sequences is the same as the cardinality of reals, and it seemed fairly intuitive to me that if cardinality of a set $A$ is strictly greater than the cardinality of the set $B$, then cardinality of $A^{mathbb{N}}$ should be strictly greater than cardinality of $B^{mathbb{N}}$. It turns out to be false.
Some technical answers have appeared in this forum elsewhere but I do not understand them. As I am not an expert in this topic, could some one explain me in simple terms why this is happening?
Also is the cardinality of all functions from reals to reals also the same as the cardinality of reals?
set-theory cardinals
$endgroup$
I was wondering what the cardinality of the set of all real sequences is. A random search through this site says that it is equal to the cardinality of the real numbers. This is very surprising to me, since the cardinality of all rational sequences is the same as the cardinality of reals, and it seemed fairly intuitive to me that if cardinality of a set $A$ is strictly greater than the cardinality of the set $B$, then cardinality of $A^{mathbb{N}}$ should be strictly greater than cardinality of $B^{mathbb{N}}$. It turns out to be false.
Some technical answers have appeared in this forum elsewhere but I do not understand them. As I am not an expert in this topic, could some one explain me in simple terms why this is happening?
Also is the cardinality of all functions from reals to reals also the same as the cardinality of reals?
set-theory cardinals
set-theory cardinals
asked Jun 7 '13 at 14:01
Vishal GuptaVishal Gupta
4,60021742
4,60021742
1
$begingroup$
Have you tried searching the site?
$endgroup$
– Asaf Karagila♦
Jun 7 '13 at 14:27
$begingroup$
Yes, I did and found some technical stuff too.
$endgroup$
– Vishal Gupta
Jun 8 '13 at 3:44
$begingroup$
@VishalGupta Can u plzz explain how |$Q^N$| =$|N|$?
$endgroup$
– sani
May 12 '17 at 19:01
add a comment |
1
$begingroup$
Have you tried searching the site?
$endgroup$
– Asaf Karagila♦
Jun 7 '13 at 14:27
$begingroup$
Yes, I did and found some technical stuff too.
$endgroup$
– Vishal Gupta
Jun 8 '13 at 3:44
$begingroup$
@VishalGupta Can u plzz explain how |$Q^N$| =$|N|$?
$endgroup$
– sani
May 12 '17 at 19:01
1
1
$begingroup$
Have you tried searching the site?
$endgroup$
– Asaf Karagila♦
Jun 7 '13 at 14:27
$begingroup$
Have you tried searching the site?
$endgroup$
– Asaf Karagila♦
Jun 7 '13 at 14:27
$begingroup$
Yes, I did and found some technical stuff too.
$endgroup$
– Vishal Gupta
Jun 8 '13 at 3:44
$begingroup$
Yes, I did and found some technical stuff too.
$endgroup$
– Vishal Gupta
Jun 8 '13 at 3:44
$begingroup$
@VishalGupta Can u plzz explain how |$Q^N$| =$|N|$?
$endgroup$
– sani
May 12 '17 at 19:01
$begingroup$
@VishalGupta Can u plzz explain how |$Q^N$| =$|N|$?
$endgroup$
– sani
May 12 '17 at 19:01
add a comment |
5 Answers
5
active
oldest
votes
$begingroup$
Identify $mathbb R$ as the set of functions $f : mathbb N to { 0,1} $.
Then any sequence ${ x_n }$ becomes a sequence ${f_n }_n$ where $f_n : mathbb N to { 0,1}$. But then, this is simply a function $g : mathbb N times mathbb N to { 0,1}$:
$$g(m,n) =f_n(m) ,.$$
This way you can construct a bijection from the sequences of real numbers to the set of functions from $mathbb N times mathbb N to { 0,1}$. Now, since $mathbb N times mathbb N$ and $mathbb N$ have the same cardinality, you get a bijection from the sequences of real numbers to the set of functions from $mathbb{N} times mathbb{N} to { 0,1}$, which is just $mathbb R$.
$endgroup$
$begingroup$
Thanks for the lovely answer.
$endgroup$
– Vishal Gupta
Jun 8 '13 at 3:40
1
$begingroup$
A lovely use of currying indeed.
$endgroup$
– Alex Vong
Jun 6 '17 at 4:37
add a comment |
$begingroup$
You asked for an explanation in "simple terms" why this is happening, which I take to mean an intuitive explanation instead of a formal proof, so that's what I'll give.
Focus on numbers between $0$ and $1$. Such a number is determined by a countable amount of information, namely the digits in its decimal expansion. So, a sequence of numbers between $0$ and $1$ is determined by a countable amount of countable information. But the countable union of countable sets is countable, so this countable amount of countable information can in turn be expressed by a countable amount of information, namely a countable number of digits. This can then be used to define a single real number between $0$ and $1$ which encodes the original sequence.
This idea can be used to give a formal proof. As for your question about functions, what do you know about the set of functions from $mathbb R$ to ${0,1}$?
$endgroup$
$begingroup$
Thanks for the very nice intuitive explanation. Yeah, I got the other question also, thanks to your hint; the cardinality is greater than equal to that of power set of real numbers. But is it equal to the cardinality of power set of real numbers?
$endgroup$
– Vishal Gupta
Jun 8 '13 at 3:42
1
$begingroup$
@Santiago Canez Can you give some intuitive idea about the converse too, that is every real sequence can be put into as numbers between 0 and 1
$endgroup$
– Saravanan
Jan 20 '17 at 9:49
add a comment |
$begingroup$
It depends on whether you are talking about finite sequences, infinite sequences, or "uncountable sequences". Here is an attempt to give you a little bit of an intuition for the mathematical territory:
If you are talking about the set of all finite real sequences, then we have the following argument: for any $n$, the cardinality of $mathbb{R}^n$ is the same as the cardinality of $mathbb{R}$ (which I will call $c$ for convenience). Thus, the set of finite sequences of a given length is a set of cardinality $c$. The cardinality of the arbitrary union of sets of cardinality $c$ gives you another set of cardinality $c$. Thus, the set of all finite sequences is of cardinality $c$. The same argument can be made regarding $mathbb{Q}$ (which has cardinality $aleph_0$)
The cardinality of infinite sequences is, however, a different story. Cantor's argument tells us that for any set $S$, we have $left| wp(S) right|>left| S right|$. For every subset of the rational numbers, there is a corresponding sequence in $mathbb{Q}^{mathbb{N}}$. Real numbers, on the other hand, are uncountable, so no infinite sequence will contain every element. So, as it ends up,
$left| mathbb{R}^{mathbb{N}} right| =left| mathbb{Q}^{mathbb{N}} right|= c$
Finally, we have the "uncountable sequences", that is, the set of functions from $mathbb{R}$ to $mathbb{R}$, which does have a greater cardinality. Here, we can use the previous argument as follows: for any subset $S subseteq mathbb{R}$, we can map $S$ to a function $f(x)$ for which $f(x)=0$ for any $xin S$. This gives us an injective map from $wp(mathbb{R})$ to the set of functions from $mathbb{R}$ to itself. Thus, the cardinality of the set of functions from $mathbb{R}$ to $mathbb{R}$ is greater than $c$.
A nice bit of cardinal arithmetic to have in your arsenal: for transfinite sets $P$ and $Q$:
$$
left| P^Qright|=max{left|Pright|,left|wp(Q)right|}
$$
EDIT: I am not sure about that last formula, let's call it a conjecture.
$endgroup$
$begingroup$
Thanks for the nice answer. But how did you say so, it ends up,$left| mathbb{R}^{mathbb{N}} right| =left| mathbb{Q}^{mathbb{N}} right|= c$? And could you give some reference to the last formula?
$endgroup$
– Vishal Gupta
Jun 8 '13 at 3:38
$begingroup$
So a little bit of elaboration on $left| mathbb{R}^{mathbb{N}} right| =left| mathbb{Q}^{mathbb{N}} right|= c$. The one on the left you know from your own research; i.e. the cardinality of the sequences of the real numbers is the same as that of the reals. The one on the right works because there's an injection from $mathbb{R}$ to $mathbb{Q}^mathbb{N}$ and another from $mathbb{Q}^mathbb{N}$ to $mathbb{R}^mathbb{N}$. I thought I had seen the last formula somewhere but now I'm not so sure.
$endgroup$
– Omnomnomnom
Jun 8 '13 at 6:21
$begingroup$
I think your formula holds under GCH. Specifically, $P^Q = beth_alpha^{beth_beta}$ in GCH, for some ordinals $alpha$ and $beta$. If $alpha$ has a predecessor $gamma$, then we have $P^Q = left ( 2^{beth_gamma} right )^{beth_beta} = 2^{max { beth_gamma,beth_beta }}= 2^{beth_{max { gamma,beta }}}$. Now if $P>mathcal{P}(Q)$ then $gamma geq beta$; if $P<mathcal{P}(Q)$ then $gamma<beta$; if $P=mathcal{P}(Q)$ then $gamma=beta$. In any of these cases we get what was wanted. I'm not sure what to do if $alpha$ is a limit ordinal.
$endgroup$
– Ian
Sep 14 '14 at 20:25
add a comment |
$begingroup$
In simple terms, our number-sense intuition comes from dealing with finite sets, and has very little value when dealing with infinite sets. This is why a set can have the same cardinality as a proper subset, and why $B^mathbb{N}$ can have the same cardinality as $A^mathbb{N}$ even if one is a proper subset of the other.
$endgroup$
$begingroup$
Thanks. But could you be a little more explanatory? Also, could you answer what is the cardinality of all real functions?
$endgroup$
– Vishal Gupta
Jun 7 '13 at 14:10
$begingroup$
For $A=mathbb{R}$, it turns out that $|A^mathbb{N}|=|A|$, as proved here.
$endgroup$
– vadim123
Jun 7 '13 at 14:12
$begingroup$
Yeah, I had seen that before posting. However, I do not understand how he got the third equality in that line.
$endgroup$
– Vishal Gupta
Jun 7 '13 at 14:19
$begingroup$
This comes from $aleph_0timesaleph_0=aleph_0$. See, e.g. here.
$endgroup$
– vadim123
Jun 7 '13 at 16:25
add a comment |
$begingroup$
Let $k,m$ be infinite cardinals. Then
$$(2^k)^m = 2^{k cdot m} = 2^{max { k,m }}.$$
Here I have used the axiom of choice in the second equality. The $max$ there causes the non-strict monotonicity that surprised you.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
Your Answer
StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function () {
return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function () {
StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix) {
StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
});
});
}, "mathjax-editing");
StackExchange.ready(function() {
var channelOptions = {
tags: "".split(" "),
id: "69"
};
initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);
StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function() {
// Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled) {
StackExchange.using("snippets", function() {
createEditor();
});
}
else {
createEditor();
}
});
function createEditor() {
StackExchange.prepareEditor({
heartbeatType: 'answer',
autoActivateHeartbeat: false,
convertImagesToLinks: true,
noModals: true,
showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
reputationToPostImages: 10,
bindNavPrevention: true,
postfix: "",
imageUploader: {
brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
allowUrls: true
},
noCode: true, onDemand: true,
discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
});
}
});
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
StackExchange.ready(
function () {
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f413836%2fcardinality-of-all-real-sequences%23new-answer', 'question_page');
}
);
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
5 Answers
5
active
oldest
votes
5 Answers
5
active
oldest
votes
active
oldest
votes
active
oldest
votes
$begingroup$
Identify $mathbb R$ as the set of functions $f : mathbb N to { 0,1} $.
Then any sequence ${ x_n }$ becomes a sequence ${f_n }_n$ where $f_n : mathbb N to { 0,1}$. But then, this is simply a function $g : mathbb N times mathbb N to { 0,1}$:
$$g(m,n) =f_n(m) ,.$$
This way you can construct a bijection from the sequences of real numbers to the set of functions from $mathbb N times mathbb N to { 0,1}$. Now, since $mathbb N times mathbb N$ and $mathbb N$ have the same cardinality, you get a bijection from the sequences of real numbers to the set of functions from $mathbb{N} times mathbb{N} to { 0,1}$, which is just $mathbb R$.
$endgroup$
$begingroup$
Thanks for the lovely answer.
$endgroup$
– Vishal Gupta
Jun 8 '13 at 3:40
1
$begingroup$
A lovely use of currying indeed.
$endgroup$
– Alex Vong
Jun 6 '17 at 4:37
add a comment |
$begingroup$
Identify $mathbb R$ as the set of functions $f : mathbb N to { 0,1} $.
Then any sequence ${ x_n }$ becomes a sequence ${f_n }_n$ where $f_n : mathbb N to { 0,1}$. But then, this is simply a function $g : mathbb N times mathbb N to { 0,1}$:
$$g(m,n) =f_n(m) ,.$$
This way you can construct a bijection from the sequences of real numbers to the set of functions from $mathbb N times mathbb N to { 0,1}$. Now, since $mathbb N times mathbb N$ and $mathbb N$ have the same cardinality, you get a bijection from the sequences of real numbers to the set of functions from $mathbb{N} times mathbb{N} to { 0,1}$, which is just $mathbb R$.
$endgroup$
$begingroup$
Thanks for the lovely answer.
$endgroup$
– Vishal Gupta
Jun 8 '13 at 3:40
1
$begingroup$
A lovely use of currying indeed.
$endgroup$
– Alex Vong
Jun 6 '17 at 4:37
add a comment |
$begingroup$
Identify $mathbb R$ as the set of functions $f : mathbb N to { 0,1} $.
Then any sequence ${ x_n }$ becomes a sequence ${f_n }_n$ where $f_n : mathbb N to { 0,1}$. But then, this is simply a function $g : mathbb N times mathbb N to { 0,1}$:
$$g(m,n) =f_n(m) ,.$$
This way you can construct a bijection from the sequences of real numbers to the set of functions from $mathbb N times mathbb N to { 0,1}$. Now, since $mathbb N times mathbb N$ and $mathbb N$ have the same cardinality, you get a bijection from the sequences of real numbers to the set of functions from $mathbb{N} times mathbb{N} to { 0,1}$, which is just $mathbb R$.
$endgroup$
Identify $mathbb R$ as the set of functions $f : mathbb N to { 0,1} $.
Then any sequence ${ x_n }$ becomes a sequence ${f_n }_n$ where $f_n : mathbb N to { 0,1}$. But then, this is simply a function $g : mathbb N times mathbb N to { 0,1}$:
$$g(m,n) =f_n(m) ,.$$
This way you can construct a bijection from the sequences of real numbers to the set of functions from $mathbb N times mathbb N to { 0,1}$. Now, since $mathbb N times mathbb N$ and $mathbb N$ have the same cardinality, you get a bijection from the sequences of real numbers to the set of functions from $mathbb{N} times mathbb{N} to { 0,1}$, which is just $mathbb R$.
edited Jun 8 '13 at 3:41
Vishal Gupta
4,60021742
4,60021742
answered Jun 7 '13 at 14:58
N. S.N. S.
103k6111208
103k6111208
$begingroup$
Thanks for the lovely answer.
$endgroup$
– Vishal Gupta
Jun 8 '13 at 3:40
1
$begingroup$
A lovely use of currying indeed.
$endgroup$
– Alex Vong
Jun 6 '17 at 4:37
add a comment |
$begingroup$
Thanks for the lovely answer.
$endgroup$
– Vishal Gupta
Jun 8 '13 at 3:40
1
$begingroup$
A lovely use of currying indeed.
$endgroup$
– Alex Vong
Jun 6 '17 at 4:37
$begingroup$
Thanks for the lovely answer.
$endgroup$
– Vishal Gupta
Jun 8 '13 at 3:40
$begingroup$
Thanks for the lovely answer.
$endgroup$
– Vishal Gupta
Jun 8 '13 at 3:40
1
1
$begingroup$
A lovely use of currying indeed.
$endgroup$
– Alex Vong
Jun 6 '17 at 4:37
$begingroup$
A lovely use of currying indeed.
$endgroup$
– Alex Vong
Jun 6 '17 at 4:37
add a comment |
$begingroup$
You asked for an explanation in "simple terms" why this is happening, which I take to mean an intuitive explanation instead of a formal proof, so that's what I'll give.
Focus on numbers between $0$ and $1$. Such a number is determined by a countable amount of information, namely the digits in its decimal expansion. So, a sequence of numbers between $0$ and $1$ is determined by a countable amount of countable information. But the countable union of countable sets is countable, so this countable amount of countable information can in turn be expressed by a countable amount of information, namely a countable number of digits. This can then be used to define a single real number between $0$ and $1$ which encodes the original sequence.
This idea can be used to give a formal proof. As for your question about functions, what do you know about the set of functions from $mathbb R$ to ${0,1}$?
$endgroup$
$begingroup$
Thanks for the very nice intuitive explanation. Yeah, I got the other question also, thanks to your hint; the cardinality is greater than equal to that of power set of real numbers. But is it equal to the cardinality of power set of real numbers?
$endgroup$
– Vishal Gupta
Jun 8 '13 at 3:42
1
$begingroup$
@Santiago Canez Can you give some intuitive idea about the converse too, that is every real sequence can be put into as numbers between 0 and 1
$endgroup$
– Saravanan
Jan 20 '17 at 9:49
add a comment |
$begingroup$
You asked for an explanation in "simple terms" why this is happening, which I take to mean an intuitive explanation instead of a formal proof, so that's what I'll give.
Focus on numbers between $0$ and $1$. Such a number is determined by a countable amount of information, namely the digits in its decimal expansion. So, a sequence of numbers between $0$ and $1$ is determined by a countable amount of countable information. But the countable union of countable sets is countable, so this countable amount of countable information can in turn be expressed by a countable amount of information, namely a countable number of digits. This can then be used to define a single real number between $0$ and $1$ which encodes the original sequence.
This idea can be used to give a formal proof. As for your question about functions, what do you know about the set of functions from $mathbb R$ to ${0,1}$?
$endgroup$
$begingroup$
Thanks for the very nice intuitive explanation. Yeah, I got the other question also, thanks to your hint; the cardinality is greater than equal to that of power set of real numbers. But is it equal to the cardinality of power set of real numbers?
$endgroup$
– Vishal Gupta
Jun 8 '13 at 3:42
1
$begingroup$
@Santiago Canez Can you give some intuitive idea about the converse too, that is every real sequence can be put into as numbers between 0 and 1
$endgroup$
– Saravanan
Jan 20 '17 at 9:49
add a comment |
$begingroup$
You asked for an explanation in "simple terms" why this is happening, which I take to mean an intuitive explanation instead of a formal proof, so that's what I'll give.
Focus on numbers between $0$ and $1$. Such a number is determined by a countable amount of information, namely the digits in its decimal expansion. So, a sequence of numbers between $0$ and $1$ is determined by a countable amount of countable information. But the countable union of countable sets is countable, so this countable amount of countable information can in turn be expressed by a countable amount of information, namely a countable number of digits. This can then be used to define a single real number between $0$ and $1$ which encodes the original sequence.
This idea can be used to give a formal proof. As for your question about functions, what do you know about the set of functions from $mathbb R$ to ${0,1}$?
$endgroup$
You asked for an explanation in "simple terms" why this is happening, which I take to mean an intuitive explanation instead of a formal proof, so that's what I'll give.
Focus on numbers between $0$ and $1$. Such a number is determined by a countable amount of information, namely the digits in its decimal expansion. So, a sequence of numbers between $0$ and $1$ is determined by a countable amount of countable information. But the countable union of countable sets is countable, so this countable amount of countable information can in turn be expressed by a countable amount of information, namely a countable number of digits. This can then be used to define a single real number between $0$ and $1$ which encodes the original sequence.
This idea can be used to give a formal proof. As for your question about functions, what do you know about the set of functions from $mathbb R$ to ${0,1}$?
answered Jun 7 '13 at 14:39
Santiago CanezSantiago Canez
2,06111113
2,06111113
$begingroup$
Thanks for the very nice intuitive explanation. Yeah, I got the other question also, thanks to your hint; the cardinality is greater than equal to that of power set of real numbers. But is it equal to the cardinality of power set of real numbers?
$endgroup$
– Vishal Gupta
Jun 8 '13 at 3:42
1
$begingroup$
@Santiago Canez Can you give some intuitive idea about the converse too, that is every real sequence can be put into as numbers between 0 and 1
$endgroup$
– Saravanan
Jan 20 '17 at 9:49
add a comment |
$begingroup$
Thanks for the very nice intuitive explanation. Yeah, I got the other question also, thanks to your hint; the cardinality is greater than equal to that of power set of real numbers. But is it equal to the cardinality of power set of real numbers?
$endgroup$
– Vishal Gupta
Jun 8 '13 at 3:42
1
$begingroup$
@Santiago Canez Can you give some intuitive idea about the converse too, that is every real sequence can be put into as numbers between 0 and 1
$endgroup$
– Saravanan
Jan 20 '17 at 9:49
$begingroup$
Thanks for the very nice intuitive explanation. Yeah, I got the other question also, thanks to your hint; the cardinality is greater than equal to that of power set of real numbers. But is it equal to the cardinality of power set of real numbers?
$endgroup$
– Vishal Gupta
Jun 8 '13 at 3:42
$begingroup$
Thanks for the very nice intuitive explanation. Yeah, I got the other question also, thanks to your hint; the cardinality is greater than equal to that of power set of real numbers. But is it equal to the cardinality of power set of real numbers?
$endgroup$
– Vishal Gupta
Jun 8 '13 at 3:42
1
1
$begingroup$
@Santiago Canez Can you give some intuitive idea about the converse too, that is every real sequence can be put into as numbers between 0 and 1
$endgroup$
– Saravanan
Jan 20 '17 at 9:49
$begingroup$
@Santiago Canez Can you give some intuitive idea about the converse too, that is every real sequence can be put into as numbers between 0 and 1
$endgroup$
– Saravanan
Jan 20 '17 at 9:49
add a comment |
$begingroup$
It depends on whether you are talking about finite sequences, infinite sequences, or "uncountable sequences". Here is an attempt to give you a little bit of an intuition for the mathematical territory:
If you are talking about the set of all finite real sequences, then we have the following argument: for any $n$, the cardinality of $mathbb{R}^n$ is the same as the cardinality of $mathbb{R}$ (which I will call $c$ for convenience). Thus, the set of finite sequences of a given length is a set of cardinality $c$. The cardinality of the arbitrary union of sets of cardinality $c$ gives you another set of cardinality $c$. Thus, the set of all finite sequences is of cardinality $c$. The same argument can be made regarding $mathbb{Q}$ (which has cardinality $aleph_0$)
The cardinality of infinite sequences is, however, a different story. Cantor's argument tells us that for any set $S$, we have $left| wp(S) right|>left| S right|$. For every subset of the rational numbers, there is a corresponding sequence in $mathbb{Q}^{mathbb{N}}$. Real numbers, on the other hand, are uncountable, so no infinite sequence will contain every element. So, as it ends up,
$left| mathbb{R}^{mathbb{N}} right| =left| mathbb{Q}^{mathbb{N}} right|= c$
Finally, we have the "uncountable sequences", that is, the set of functions from $mathbb{R}$ to $mathbb{R}$, which does have a greater cardinality. Here, we can use the previous argument as follows: for any subset $S subseteq mathbb{R}$, we can map $S$ to a function $f(x)$ for which $f(x)=0$ for any $xin S$. This gives us an injective map from $wp(mathbb{R})$ to the set of functions from $mathbb{R}$ to itself. Thus, the cardinality of the set of functions from $mathbb{R}$ to $mathbb{R}$ is greater than $c$.
A nice bit of cardinal arithmetic to have in your arsenal: for transfinite sets $P$ and $Q$:
$$
left| P^Qright|=max{left|Pright|,left|wp(Q)right|}
$$
EDIT: I am not sure about that last formula, let's call it a conjecture.
$endgroup$
$begingroup$
Thanks for the nice answer. But how did you say so, it ends up,$left| mathbb{R}^{mathbb{N}} right| =left| mathbb{Q}^{mathbb{N}} right|= c$? And could you give some reference to the last formula?
$endgroup$
– Vishal Gupta
Jun 8 '13 at 3:38
$begingroup$
So a little bit of elaboration on $left| mathbb{R}^{mathbb{N}} right| =left| mathbb{Q}^{mathbb{N}} right|= c$. The one on the left you know from your own research; i.e. the cardinality of the sequences of the real numbers is the same as that of the reals. The one on the right works because there's an injection from $mathbb{R}$ to $mathbb{Q}^mathbb{N}$ and another from $mathbb{Q}^mathbb{N}$ to $mathbb{R}^mathbb{N}$. I thought I had seen the last formula somewhere but now I'm not so sure.
$endgroup$
– Omnomnomnom
Jun 8 '13 at 6:21
$begingroup$
I think your formula holds under GCH. Specifically, $P^Q = beth_alpha^{beth_beta}$ in GCH, for some ordinals $alpha$ and $beta$. If $alpha$ has a predecessor $gamma$, then we have $P^Q = left ( 2^{beth_gamma} right )^{beth_beta} = 2^{max { beth_gamma,beth_beta }}= 2^{beth_{max { gamma,beta }}}$. Now if $P>mathcal{P}(Q)$ then $gamma geq beta$; if $P<mathcal{P}(Q)$ then $gamma<beta$; if $P=mathcal{P}(Q)$ then $gamma=beta$. In any of these cases we get what was wanted. I'm not sure what to do if $alpha$ is a limit ordinal.
$endgroup$
– Ian
Sep 14 '14 at 20:25
add a comment |
$begingroup$
It depends on whether you are talking about finite sequences, infinite sequences, or "uncountable sequences". Here is an attempt to give you a little bit of an intuition for the mathematical territory:
If you are talking about the set of all finite real sequences, then we have the following argument: for any $n$, the cardinality of $mathbb{R}^n$ is the same as the cardinality of $mathbb{R}$ (which I will call $c$ for convenience). Thus, the set of finite sequences of a given length is a set of cardinality $c$. The cardinality of the arbitrary union of sets of cardinality $c$ gives you another set of cardinality $c$. Thus, the set of all finite sequences is of cardinality $c$. The same argument can be made regarding $mathbb{Q}$ (which has cardinality $aleph_0$)
The cardinality of infinite sequences is, however, a different story. Cantor's argument tells us that for any set $S$, we have $left| wp(S) right|>left| S right|$. For every subset of the rational numbers, there is a corresponding sequence in $mathbb{Q}^{mathbb{N}}$. Real numbers, on the other hand, are uncountable, so no infinite sequence will contain every element. So, as it ends up,
$left| mathbb{R}^{mathbb{N}} right| =left| mathbb{Q}^{mathbb{N}} right|= c$
Finally, we have the "uncountable sequences", that is, the set of functions from $mathbb{R}$ to $mathbb{R}$, which does have a greater cardinality. Here, we can use the previous argument as follows: for any subset $S subseteq mathbb{R}$, we can map $S$ to a function $f(x)$ for which $f(x)=0$ for any $xin S$. This gives us an injective map from $wp(mathbb{R})$ to the set of functions from $mathbb{R}$ to itself. Thus, the cardinality of the set of functions from $mathbb{R}$ to $mathbb{R}$ is greater than $c$.
A nice bit of cardinal arithmetic to have in your arsenal: for transfinite sets $P$ and $Q$:
$$
left| P^Qright|=max{left|Pright|,left|wp(Q)right|}
$$
EDIT: I am not sure about that last formula, let's call it a conjecture.
$endgroup$
$begingroup$
Thanks for the nice answer. But how did you say so, it ends up,$left| mathbb{R}^{mathbb{N}} right| =left| mathbb{Q}^{mathbb{N}} right|= c$? And could you give some reference to the last formula?
$endgroup$
– Vishal Gupta
Jun 8 '13 at 3:38
$begingroup$
So a little bit of elaboration on $left| mathbb{R}^{mathbb{N}} right| =left| mathbb{Q}^{mathbb{N}} right|= c$. The one on the left you know from your own research; i.e. the cardinality of the sequences of the real numbers is the same as that of the reals. The one on the right works because there's an injection from $mathbb{R}$ to $mathbb{Q}^mathbb{N}$ and another from $mathbb{Q}^mathbb{N}$ to $mathbb{R}^mathbb{N}$. I thought I had seen the last formula somewhere but now I'm not so sure.
$endgroup$
– Omnomnomnom
Jun 8 '13 at 6:21
$begingroup$
I think your formula holds under GCH. Specifically, $P^Q = beth_alpha^{beth_beta}$ in GCH, for some ordinals $alpha$ and $beta$. If $alpha$ has a predecessor $gamma$, then we have $P^Q = left ( 2^{beth_gamma} right )^{beth_beta} = 2^{max { beth_gamma,beth_beta }}= 2^{beth_{max { gamma,beta }}}$. Now if $P>mathcal{P}(Q)$ then $gamma geq beta$; if $P<mathcal{P}(Q)$ then $gamma<beta$; if $P=mathcal{P}(Q)$ then $gamma=beta$. In any of these cases we get what was wanted. I'm not sure what to do if $alpha$ is a limit ordinal.
$endgroup$
– Ian
Sep 14 '14 at 20:25
add a comment |
$begingroup$
It depends on whether you are talking about finite sequences, infinite sequences, or "uncountable sequences". Here is an attempt to give you a little bit of an intuition for the mathematical territory:
If you are talking about the set of all finite real sequences, then we have the following argument: for any $n$, the cardinality of $mathbb{R}^n$ is the same as the cardinality of $mathbb{R}$ (which I will call $c$ for convenience). Thus, the set of finite sequences of a given length is a set of cardinality $c$. The cardinality of the arbitrary union of sets of cardinality $c$ gives you another set of cardinality $c$. Thus, the set of all finite sequences is of cardinality $c$. The same argument can be made regarding $mathbb{Q}$ (which has cardinality $aleph_0$)
The cardinality of infinite sequences is, however, a different story. Cantor's argument tells us that for any set $S$, we have $left| wp(S) right|>left| S right|$. For every subset of the rational numbers, there is a corresponding sequence in $mathbb{Q}^{mathbb{N}}$. Real numbers, on the other hand, are uncountable, so no infinite sequence will contain every element. So, as it ends up,
$left| mathbb{R}^{mathbb{N}} right| =left| mathbb{Q}^{mathbb{N}} right|= c$
Finally, we have the "uncountable sequences", that is, the set of functions from $mathbb{R}$ to $mathbb{R}$, which does have a greater cardinality. Here, we can use the previous argument as follows: for any subset $S subseteq mathbb{R}$, we can map $S$ to a function $f(x)$ for which $f(x)=0$ for any $xin S$. This gives us an injective map from $wp(mathbb{R})$ to the set of functions from $mathbb{R}$ to itself. Thus, the cardinality of the set of functions from $mathbb{R}$ to $mathbb{R}$ is greater than $c$.
A nice bit of cardinal arithmetic to have in your arsenal: for transfinite sets $P$ and $Q$:
$$
left| P^Qright|=max{left|Pright|,left|wp(Q)right|}
$$
EDIT: I am not sure about that last formula, let's call it a conjecture.
$endgroup$
It depends on whether you are talking about finite sequences, infinite sequences, or "uncountable sequences". Here is an attempt to give you a little bit of an intuition for the mathematical territory:
If you are talking about the set of all finite real sequences, then we have the following argument: for any $n$, the cardinality of $mathbb{R}^n$ is the same as the cardinality of $mathbb{R}$ (which I will call $c$ for convenience). Thus, the set of finite sequences of a given length is a set of cardinality $c$. The cardinality of the arbitrary union of sets of cardinality $c$ gives you another set of cardinality $c$. Thus, the set of all finite sequences is of cardinality $c$. The same argument can be made regarding $mathbb{Q}$ (which has cardinality $aleph_0$)
The cardinality of infinite sequences is, however, a different story. Cantor's argument tells us that for any set $S$, we have $left| wp(S) right|>left| S right|$. For every subset of the rational numbers, there is a corresponding sequence in $mathbb{Q}^{mathbb{N}}$. Real numbers, on the other hand, are uncountable, so no infinite sequence will contain every element. So, as it ends up,
$left| mathbb{R}^{mathbb{N}} right| =left| mathbb{Q}^{mathbb{N}} right|= c$
Finally, we have the "uncountable sequences", that is, the set of functions from $mathbb{R}$ to $mathbb{R}$, which does have a greater cardinality. Here, we can use the previous argument as follows: for any subset $S subseteq mathbb{R}$, we can map $S$ to a function $f(x)$ for which $f(x)=0$ for any $xin S$. This gives us an injective map from $wp(mathbb{R})$ to the set of functions from $mathbb{R}$ to itself. Thus, the cardinality of the set of functions from $mathbb{R}$ to $mathbb{R}$ is greater than $c$.
A nice bit of cardinal arithmetic to have in your arsenal: for transfinite sets $P$ and $Q$:
$$
left| P^Qright|=max{left|Pright|,left|wp(Q)right|}
$$
EDIT: I am not sure about that last formula, let's call it a conjecture.
edited Jun 8 '13 at 6:15
answered Jun 7 '13 at 14:42
OmnomnomnomOmnomnomnom
127k790178
127k790178
$begingroup$
Thanks for the nice answer. But how did you say so, it ends up,$left| mathbb{R}^{mathbb{N}} right| =left| mathbb{Q}^{mathbb{N}} right|= c$? And could you give some reference to the last formula?
$endgroup$
– Vishal Gupta
Jun 8 '13 at 3:38
$begingroup$
So a little bit of elaboration on $left| mathbb{R}^{mathbb{N}} right| =left| mathbb{Q}^{mathbb{N}} right|= c$. The one on the left you know from your own research; i.e. the cardinality of the sequences of the real numbers is the same as that of the reals. The one on the right works because there's an injection from $mathbb{R}$ to $mathbb{Q}^mathbb{N}$ and another from $mathbb{Q}^mathbb{N}$ to $mathbb{R}^mathbb{N}$. I thought I had seen the last formula somewhere but now I'm not so sure.
$endgroup$
– Omnomnomnom
Jun 8 '13 at 6:21
$begingroup$
I think your formula holds under GCH. Specifically, $P^Q = beth_alpha^{beth_beta}$ in GCH, for some ordinals $alpha$ and $beta$. If $alpha$ has a predecessor $gamma$, then we have $P^Q = left ( 2^{beth_gamma} right )^{beth_beta} = 2^{max { beth_gamma,beth_beta }}= 2^{beth_{max { gamma,beta }}}$. Now if $P>mathcal{P}(Q)$ then $gamma geq beta$; if $P<mathcal{P}(Q)$ then $gamma<beta$; if $P=mathcal{P}(Q)$ then $gamma=beta$. In any of these cases we get what was wanted. I'm not sure what to do if $alpha$ is a limit ordinal.
$endgroup$
– Ian
Sep 14 '14 at 20:25
add a comment |
$begingroup$
Thanks for the nice answer. But how did you say so, it ends up,$left| mathbb{R}^{mathbb{N}} right| =left| mathbb{Q}^{mathbb{N}} right|= c$? And could you give some reference to the last formula?
$endgroup$
– Vishal Gupta
Jun 8 '13 at 3:38
$begingroup$
So a little bit of elaboration on $left| mathbb{R}^{mathbb{N}} right| =left| mathbb{Q}^{mathbb{N}} right|= c$. The one on the left you know from your own research; i.e. the cardinality of the sequences of the real numbers is the same as that of the reals. The one on the right works because there's an injection from $mathbb{R}$ to $mathbb{Q}^mathbb{N}$ and another from $mathbb{Q}^mathbb{N}$ to $mathbb{R}^mathbb{N}$. I thought I had seen the last formula somewhere but now I'm not so sure.
$endgroup$
– Omnomnomnom
Jun 8 '13 at 6:21
$begingroup$
I think your formula holds under GCH. Specifically, $P^Q = beth_alpha^{beth_beta}$ in GCH, for some ordinals $alpha$ and $beta$. If $alpha$ has a predecessor $gamma$, then we have $P^Q = left ( 2^{beth_gamma} right )^{beth_beta} = 2^{max { beth_gamma,beth_beta }}= 2^{beth_{max { gamma,beta }}}$. Now if $P>mathcal{P}(Q)$ then $gamma geq beta$; if $P<mathcal{P}(Q)$ then $gamma<beta$; if $P=mathcal{P}(Q)$ then $gamma=beta$. In any of these cases we get what was wanted. I'm not sure what to do if $alpha$ is a limit ordinal.
$endgroup$
– Ian
Sep 14 '14 at 20:25
$begingroup$
Thanks for the nice answer. But how did you say so, it ends up,$left| mathbb{R}^{mathbb{N}} right| =left| mathbb{Q}^{mathbb{N}} right|= c$? And could you give some reference to the last formula?
$endgroup$
– Vishal Gupta
Jun 8 '13 at 3:38
$begingroup$
Thanks for the nice answer. But how did you say so, it ends up,$left| mathbb{R}^{mathbb{N}} right| =left| mathbb{Q}^{mathbb{N}} right|= c$? And could you give some reference to the last formula?
$endgroup$
– Vishal Gupta
Jun 8 '13 at 3:38
$begingroup$
So a little bit of elaboration on $left| mathbb{R}^{mathbb{N}} right| =left| mathbb{Q}^{mathbb{N}} right|= c$. The one on the left you know from your own research; i.e. the cardinality of the sequences of the real numbers is the same as that of the reals. The one on the right works because there's an injection from $mathbb{R}$ to $mathbb{Q}^mathbb{N}$ and another from $mathbb{Q}^mathbb{N}$ to $mathbb{R}^mathbb{N}$. I thought I had seen the last formula somewhere but now I'm not so sure.
$endgroup$
– Omnomnomnom
Jun 8 '13 at 6:21
$begingroup$
So a little bit of elaboration on $left| mathbb{R}^{mathbb{N}} right| =left| mathbb{Q}^{mathbb{N}} right|= c$. The one on the left you know from your own research; i.e. the cardinality of the sequences of the real numbers is the same as that of the reals. The one on the right works because there's an injection from $mathbb{R}$ to $mathbb{Q}^mathbb{N}$ and another from $mathbb{Q}^mathbb{N}$ to $mathbb{R}^mathbb{N}$. I thought I had seen the last formula somewhere but now I'm not so sure.
$endgroup$
– Omnomnomnom
Jun 8 '13 at 6:21
$begingroup$
I think your formula holds under GCH. Specifically, $P^Q = beth_alpha^{beth_beta}$ in GCH, for some ordinals $alpha$ and $beta$. If $alpha$ has a predecessor $gamma$, then we have $P^Q = left ( 2^{beth_gamma} right )^{beth_beta} = 2^{max { beth_gamma,beth_beta }}= 2^{beth_{max { gamma,beta }}}$. Now if $P>mathcal{P}(Q)$ then $gamma geq beta$; if $P<mathcal{P}(Q)$ then $gamma<beta$; if $P=mathcal{P}(Q)$ then $gamma=beta$. In any of these cases we get what was wanted. I'm not sure what to do if $alpha$ is a limit ordinal.
$endgroup$
– Ian
Sep 14 '14 at 20:25
$begingroup$
I think your formula holds under GCH. Specifically, $P^Q = beth_alpha^{beth_beta}$ in GCH, for some ordinals $alpha$ and $beta$. If $alpha$ has a predecessor $gamma$, then we have $P^Q = left ( 2^{beth_gamma} right )^{beth_beta} = 2^{max { beth_gamma,beth_beta }}= 2^{beth_{max { gamma,beta }}}$. Now if $P>mathcal{P}(Q)$ then $gamma geq beta$; if $P<mathcal{P}(Q)$ then $gamma<beta$; if $P=mathcal{P}(Q)$ then $gamma=beta$. In any of these cases we get what was wanted. I'm not sure what to do if $alpha$ is a limit ordinal.
$endgroup$
– Ian
Sep 14 '14 at 20:25
add a comment |
$begingroup$
In simple terms, our number-sense intuition comes from dealing with finite sets, and has very little value when dealing with infinite sets. This is why a set can have the same cardinality as a proper subset, and why $B^mathbb{N}$ can have the same cardinality as $A^mathbb{N}$ even if one is a proper subset of the other.
$endgroup$
$begingroup$
Thanks. But could you be a little more explanatory? Also, could you answer what is the cardinality of all real functions?
$endgroup$
– Vishal Gupta
Jun 7 '13 at 14:10
$begingroup$
For $A=mathbb{R}$, it turns out that $|A^mathbb{N}|=|A|$, as proved here.
$endgroup$
– vadim123
Jun 7 '13 at 14:12
$begingroup$
Yeah, I had seen that before posting. However, I do not understand how he got the third equality in that line.
$endgroup$
– Vishal Gupta
Jun 7 '13 at 14:19
$begingroup$
This comes from $aleph_0timesaleph_0=aleph_0$. See, e.g. here.
$endgroup$
– vadim123
Jun 7 '13 at 16:25
add a comment |
$begingroup$
In simple terms, our number-sense intuition comes from dealing with finite sets, and has very little value when dealing with infinite sets. This is why a set can have the same cardinality as a proper subset, and why $B^mathbb{N}$ can have the same cardinality as $A^mathbb{N}$ even if one is a proper subset of the other.
$endgroup$
$begingroup$
Thanks. But could you be a little more explanatory? Also, could you answer what is the cardinality of all real functions?
$endgroup$
– Vishal Gupta
Jun 7 '13 at 14:10
$begingroup$
For $A=mathbb{R}$, it turns out that $|A^mathbb{N}|=|A|$, as proved here.
$endgroup$
– vadim123
Jun 7 '13 at 14:12
$begingroup$
Yeah, I had seen that before posting. However, I do not understand how he got the third equality in that line.
$endgroup$
– Vishal Gupta
Jun 7 '13 at 14:19
$begingroup$
This comes from $aleph_0timesaleph_0=aleph_0$. See, e.g. here.
$endgroup$
– vadim123
Jun 7 '13 at 16:25
add a comment |
$begingroup$
In simple terms, our number-sense intuition comes from dealing with finite sets, and has very little value when dealing with infinite sets. This is why a set can have the same cardinality as a proper subset, and why $B^mathbb{N}$ can have the same cardinality as $A^mathbb{N}$ even if one is a proper subset of the other.
$endgroup$
In simple terms, our number-sense intuition comes from dealing with finite sets, and has very little value when dealing with infinite sets. This is why a set can have the same cardinality as a proper subset, and why $B^mathbb{N}$ can have the same cardinality as $A^mathbb{N}$ even if one is a proper subset of the other.
answered Jun 7 '13 at 14:08
vadim123vadim123
75.9k897189
75.9k897189
$begingroup$
Thanks. But could you be a little more explanatory? Also, could you answer what is the cardinality of all real functions?
$endgroup$
– Vishal Gupta
Jun 7 '13 at 14:10
$begingroup$
For $A=mathbb{R}$, it turns out that $|A^mathbb{N}|=|A|$, as proved here.
$endgroup$
– vadim123
Jun 7 '13 at 14:12
$begingroup$
Yeah, I had seen that before posting. However, I do not understand how he got the third equality in that line.
$endgroup$
– Vishal Gupta
Jun 7 '13 at 14:19
$begingroup$
This comes from $aleph_0timesaleph_0=aleph_0$. See, e.g. here.
$endgroup$
– vadim123
Jun 7 '13 at 16:25
add a comment |
$begingroup$
Thanks. But could you be a little more explanatory? Also, could you answer what is the cardinality of all real functions?
$endgroup$
– Vishal Gupta
Jun 7 '13 at 14:10
$begingroup$
For $A=mathbb{R}$, it turns out that $|A^mathbb{N}|=|A|$, as proved here.
$endgroup$
– vadim123
Jun 7 '13 at 14:12
$begingroup$
Yeah, I had seen that before posting. However, I do not understand how he got the third equality in that line.
$endgroup$
– Vishal Gupta
Jun 7 '13 at 14:19
$begingroup$
This comes from $aleph_0timesaleph_0=aleph_0$. See, e.g. here.
$endgroup$
– vadim123
Jun 7 '13 at 16:25
$begingroup$
Thanks. But could you be a little more explanatory? Also, could you answer what is the cardinality of all real functions?
$endgroup$
– Vishal Gupta
Jun 7 '13 at 14:10
$begingroup$
Thanks. But could you be a little more explanatory? Also, could you answer what is the cardinality of all real functions?
$endgroup$
– Vishal Gupta
Jun 7 '13 at 14:10
$begingroup$
For $A=mathbb{R}$, it turns out that $|A^mathbb{N}|=|A|$, as proved here.
$endgroup$
– vadim123
Jun 7 '13 at 14:12
$begingroup$
For $A=mathbb{R}$, it turns out that $|A^mathbb{N}|=|A|$, as proved here.
$endgroup$
– vadim123
Jun 7 '13 at 14:12
$begingroup$
Yeah, I had seen that before posting. However, I do not understand how he got the third equality in that line.
$endgroup$
– Vishal Gupta
Jun 7 '13 at 14:19
$begingroup$
Yeah, I had seen that before posting. However, I do not understand how he got the third equality in that line.
$endgroup$
– Vishal Gupta
Jun 7 '13 at 14:19
$begingroup$
This comes from $aleph_0timesaleph_0=aleph_0$. See, e.g. here.
$endgroup$
– vadim123
Jun 7 '13 at 16:25
$begingroup$
This comes from $aleph_0timesaleph_0=aleph_0$. See, e.g. here.
$endgroup$
– vadim123
Jun 7 '13 at 16:25
add a comment |
$begingroup$
Let $k,m$ be infinite cardinals. Then
$$(2^k)^m = 2^{k cdot m} = 2^{max { k,m }}.$$
Here I have used the axiom of choice in the second equality. The $max$ there causes the non-strict monotonicity that surprised you.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
Let $k,m$ be infinite cardinals. Then
$$(2^k)^m = 2^{k cdot m} = 2^{max { k,m }}.$$
Here I have used the axiom of choice in the second equality. The $max$ there causes the non-strict monotonicity that surprised you.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
Let $k,m$ be infinite cardinals. Then
$$(2^k)^m = 2^{k cdot m} = 2^{max { k,m }}.$$
Here I have used the axiom of choice in the second equality. The $max$ there causes the non-strict monotonicity that surprised you.
$endgroup$
Let $k,m$ be infinite cardinals. Then
$$(2^k)^m = 2^{k cdot m} = 2^{max { k,m }}.$$
Here I have used the axiom of choice in the second equality. The $max$ there causes the non-strict monotonicity that surprised you.
answered Sep 14 '14 at 20:08
IanIan
67.8k25388
67.8k25388
add a comment |
add a comment |
Thanks for contributing an answer to Mathematics Stack Exchange!
- Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!
But avoid …
- Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.
- Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.
Use MathJax to format equations. MathJax reference.
To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
StackExchange.ready(
function () {
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f413836%2fcardinality-of-all-real-sequences%23new-answer', 'question_page');
}
);
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
1
$begingroup$
Have you tried searching the site?
$endgroup$
– Asaf Karagila♦
Jun 7 '13 at 14:27
$begingroup$
Yes, I did and found some technical stuff too.
$endgroup$
– Vishal Gupta
Jun 8 '13 at 3:44
$begingroup$
@VishalGupta Can u plzz explain how |$Q^N$| =$|N|$?
$endgroup$
– sani
May 12 '17 at 19:01